Not signed in (Sign In)

Not signed in

Want to take part in these discussions? Sign in if you have an account, or apply for one below

  • Sign in using OpenID

Site Tag Cloud

2-category 2-category-theory abelian-categories adjoint algebra algebraic algebraic-geometry algebraic-topology analysis analytic-geometry arithmetic arithmetic-geometry book bundles calculus categorical categories category category-theory chern-weil-theory cohesion cohesive-homotopy-type-theory cohomology colimits combinatorics comma complex complex-geometry computable-mathematics computer-science constructive cosmology deformation-theory descent diagrams differential differential-cohomology differential-equations differential-geometry digraphs duality elliptic-cohomology enriched fibration finite foundation foundations functional-analysis functor gauge-theory gebra geometric-quantization geometry graph graphs gravity grothendieck group group-theory harmonic-analysis higher higher-algebra higher-category-theory higher-differential-geometry higher-geometry higher-lie-theory higher-topos-theory homological homological-algebra homotopy homotopy-theory homotopy-type-theory index-theory integration integration-theory k-theory lie-theory limits linear linear-algebra locale localization logic mathematics measure-theory modal modal-logic model model-category-theory monad monads monoidal monoidal-category-theory morphism motives motivic-cohomology nlab noncommutative noncommutative-geometry number-theory of operads operator operator-algebra order-theory pages pasting philosophy physics pro-object probability probability-theory quantization quantum quantum-field quantum-field-theory quantum-mechanics quantum-physics quantum-theory question representation representation-theory riemannian-geometry scheme schemes set set-theory sheaf simplicial space spin-geometry stable-homotopy-theory stack string string-theory superalgebra supergeometry svg symplectic-geometry synthetic-differential-geometry terminology theory topology topos topos-theory tqft type type-theory universal variational-calculus

Vanilla 1.1.10 is a product of Lussumo. More Information: Documentation, Community Support.

Welcome to nForum
If you want to take part in these discussions either sign in now (if you have an account), apply for one now (if you don't).
    • CommentRowNumber1.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeOct 16th 2010

    As an outcome of recent discussion at Math Overflow here, Mike Shulman suggested some nLab pages where comparisons of different definitions of compactness are rigorously established. I have created one such page: compactness and stable closure. (The importance and significance of the stable closure condition should be brought out better.)

    • CommentRowNumber2.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeJul 18th 2014

    I have added to the Properties-section at compact space that in Hausdorff space every compact subset is closed.

    • CommentRowNumber3.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeMar 31st 2016
    • (edited Mar 31st 2016)

    I have tried to edit compact space just a little for readability.

    For one, I tried to highlight nets over proper filters just a tad more (moving the statements for nets out of parenthesis, adding reminder to the equivalence via their eventuality filters), just so that the entry gets at least a little closer to giving the reader the expected statement about convergence of sequences.

    Also I pre-fixed the text of all of the many equivalent definitions by “XX is compact if…” to make it read more like a text meant for public consumption, and less like a personal note.

    • CommentRowNumber4.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeMar 31st 2016

    Looks good!

    • CommentRowNumber5.
    • CommentAuthorMike Shulman
    • CommentTimeNov 19th 2016

    I am confused about the constructive notion of “compact locale”. In the Elephant just before C3.2.8, Johnstone says

    If XX is a locale in a Boolean topos, then the unique locale map γ:X1\gamma:X\to 1 is proper iff γ *\gamma_* preserves directed joins… Constructively, the Frobenius reciprocity condition [f *(Uf *(V))=f *(U)Vf_*(U\cup f^*(V)) = f_*(U)\cup V]… is a nontrivial restriction even on locale maps with codomain 1; so we include it in the definition of compactness — that is, we define XX to be compact if X1X\to 1 is proper.

    However, as far as I can tell this additional Frobenius condition is not included in the general definition of proper geometric morphism, which just says (in the stack semantics of EE) that f:FEf:F\to E preserves directed unions of subterminals. It makes sense that some extra condition is necessary when speaking externally about a general locale map f:XYf:X\to Y, since “f *f_* preserves directed unions” is not internalized to the stack semantics of Sh(Y)Sh(Y). However, when talking about a map X1X\to 1, we should already be in the stack semantics of Sh(1)=SetSh(1) = Set. So I don’t understand why we need the Frobenius condition separately in the constructive definition of “compact locale”. Johnstone doesn’t give an example, and I don’t have Moerdijk or Vermuelen’s papers.

    On the other hand, I don’t see how to prove the Frobenius condition either. I have looked through section C3.2 of the Elephant as carefully as I can, and I haven’t been able to extract an actual proof that a proper geometric morphism between localic toposes satisfies the Frobenius condition to be a proper map of locales. Prior to defining proper geometric morphisms, he says

    …we may reasonably define a geometric morphism f:FEf:F\to E to be proper if… f *(Ω F)f_*(\Omega_F) is a compact internal frame in EE. What does it mean to say that an internal frame… is compact in a general topos EE? For the case E=SetE=Set, we saw how to answer this in topos-theoretic terms in 1.5.5: it means that the direct image functor Sh(X)SetSh(X) \to Set… preserves directed colimits of subterminal objects.

    and then proceeds to define f:FEf:F\to E to be proper if “f *f_* preserves directed colimits of subterminal objects” is true in the stack semantics of EE. But C1.5.5 used “f *f_* preserves directed unions” as a definition of “compact locale”, which the first quote above claims is not sufficient constructively, i.e. over a general base EE. So I am confused; can anyone help?

    • CommentRowNumber6.
    • CommentAuthorMike Shulman
    • CommentTimeNov 30th 2016

    Ok, I found Vermeulen’s paper, and I believe he has a constructive proof that if r:X1r:X\to 1 preserves directed joins then it satisfies the Frobenius condition. Suppose UO(X)U\in O(X) and VO(1)=ΩV\in O(1) = \Omega; we must show that if r *(Ur *(V))r_\ast(U \cup r_\ast(V)) is true, then so is r *(U)Vr_\ast(U) \cup V. Note that r *(W)r_\ast(W) is the truth value of the statement “W=XW=X”, while r *(P)={XP}r^*(P) = \bigcup \{ X \mid P \} . Suppose r *(Ur *(V))r_\ast(U \cup r_\ast(V)), i.e. that U{XV}=XU\cup \bigcup \{ X \mid V \} = X. Now consider the set {WO(X)V(WU)}\{ W\in O(X) \mid V \vee (W\le U) \}; this is evidently directed, and our supposition in the last sentence says exactly that its union is XX. Therefore, if XX is compact in the sense that its top element is inaccessible by directed joins, there exists a WW such that V(WU)V \vee (W\le U) and XWX\le W. In other words, either VV or XUX\le U, i.e. either VV or r *(U)r_\ast(U), which is what we wanted.

    So my current conclusion is that the first Elephant quote above is wrong about the Frobenius condition being an additional restriction constructively. This did seem like the most likely resolution, since otherwise the definition of proper geometric morphism would probably be wrong, which seems unlikely.

    • CommentRowNumber7.
    • CommentAuthorMike Shulman
    • CommentTimeDec 1st 2016

    I have added this proof to covert space, with pointers to it from compact space and proper map.

    • CommentRowNumber8.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeApr 23rd 2017
    • (edited Apr 23rd 2017)

    There seems to be something wrong right at the beginning of compact space:

    After def. 2.1, the usual definition about existence of finite open subcovers, there is def. 2.2 which is the immediate reformulation in terms of closed subsets: a collection of closed subsets whose intersection is empty has a finite subcollection whose intersection is still empty.

    But this def. 2.2 is introduced with the remark that it needs excluded middle to be equivalent to 2.1, which is not true.

    Probably what that remark about excluded middle was meant to refer to is instead the further formulation in terms of closed subsets, the one which says that a collection of closed subsets with the finite intersection property has non-empty intersection.

    [edit: I have added what seems to be missing at compact space to finite intersection property]

    • CommentRowNumber9.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeApr 23rd 2017
    • (edited Apr 23rd 2017)

    How are closed sets being defined here?

    If we are defining closed sets to be precisely the complements of open sets (in symbols, ¬U\neg U), then I can see that the usual open set formulation implies the closed set formulation you just mentioned: if iIU i=X\bigcup_{i \in I} U_i = X, then surely iI¬U i=¬( iU i)=¬X=\bigcap_{i \in I} \neg U_i = \neg \left(\bigcup_{i \in } U_i \right) = \neg X = \emptyset since ¬\neg takes unions to intersections.

    But then how would we turn this implication around (to assert equivalence of the two formulations)? Without excluded middle, I don’t see how every open set UU would be the complement of a closed set.

    • CommentRowNumber10.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeApr 23rd 2017

    Oh, okay. I’ll make all that explicit in the entry now.

    • CommentRowNumber11.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeApr 23rd 2017

    Okay, I have edited statement and proof at compact+space#fip. I made explicit the use of excluded middle for identifying opens with complements of closed subsets, and a second use of excluded middle for getting what is usually labeled “fip”, which is the contrapositive of what was formerly stated here.

    • CommentRowNumber12.
    • CommentAuthorMike Shulman
    • CommentTimeApr 23rd 2017

    FWIW, constructively there are at least two distinct definitions of closed set.

    • CommentRowNumber13.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeMay 14th 2017

    I have added some elementary details at compact space – Examples – General, such as the proof that closed intervals are compact.

    • CommentRowNumber14.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeMay 15th 2017

    I have added the statement about unions and intersections of compact subspaces, here

    • CommentRowNumber15.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeJun 3rd 2017

    In accordance with a recent discussion, I moved the detailed elementary proof of the example of closed intervals to its own page. Also, I added the example of cofinite topology to compact space.

    • CommentRowNumber16.
    • CommentAuthortphyahoo
    • CommentTimeJul 2nd 2017
    Proposition 3.2. (complements of compact with open subspaces is compact)

    seems wrong.

    Take [0,3] as compact space and (1,3) as subspace of R1.

    The complement is two half open spaces: [0,1) and (2,3] and by nonexample 4.6 "half open intervals are not compact"

    Either proposition 3.2 is wrong or I am missing some intuition. A proof or a reference to a proof would help clear this up if I am wrong here.
    • CommentRowNumber17.
    • CommentAuthortphyahoo
    • CommentTimeJul 2nd 2017
    • (edited Jul 2nd 2017)
    Definition 2.4, point 4 is
    "For every topological space (Y,τY) (Y,\tau_Y) the projection map out of the product topological space πY:(X×Y,τX×Y)→(Y,τY) \pi_Y \;\colon\; (X \times Y, \tau_{X \times Y}) \to (Y, \tau_Y) is a closed map.

    and proof of this is stated as
    "The proof of the equivalence of statement 4 is discussed at closed-projection characterization of compactness."

    further down

    Definition 2.10. (closed-projection characterization of compactness) is
    "X X is compact iff for any space Y Y, the projection map X×Y→Y X \times Y \to Y out of their Cartesian product is closed (see e.g. Milne, section 17)."

    Aren't these two ways of saying the same thing?

    Proposed fix: 2.4, point 4 and its proof should be deleted from 2.4 and merged to 2.10.

    Possible issue, assuming validity of above fix:

    Does 2.10 then require excluded middle?
    It is claimed that point 2.4 point 4 requires excluded middle, but it is not clear why this is.
    In fact linked "closed-projection characterization of compactness" claims a means of circumventing both excluded middle. My guess is excluded middle is not required but I don't know.
    • CommentRowNumber18.
    • CommentAuthorMike Shulman
    • CommentTimeJul 2nd 2017
    • (edited Jul 2nd 2017)

    Re: #16, [0,3](1,3)[0,3] \setminus (1,3) is [0,1]{3}[0,1] \cup \{3\}, which is compact.

    • CommentRowNumber19.
    • CommentAuthorMike Shulman
    • CommentTimeJul 2nd 2017

    Re: #17, I think you’re right that 2.4(4) and 2.10 are redundant. I don’t have an opinion on which of them should be kept.

    • CommentRowNumber20.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeJul 3rd 2017

    I have now spelled out a detailed proof of prop. 3.2 here.

    • CommentRowNumber21.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeJul 3rd 2017

    Regarding the duplication of the statement of the closed-projection characterization of compactness:

    I have removed item 4 from prop. 2.4, but I also moved the former “Definition” 2.10 up to what is now prop. 2.5, so that it is still the next statement after item 3 of prop. 2.4.

    (Todd should please have a look.)

    My main request about this entry is: Somebody should turn the long list of “Definitions” 2.7 to 2.13 of compactness into a list of propositions that state that certain statements are equivalent.

    • CommentRowNumber22.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeJul 3rd 2017

    Thanks, Urs. It looks good to me. Does the mention of excluded middle now make sense to tphyahoo? To circumvent excluded middle (as in closed-projection characterization of compactness), one has to change the statement to say the dual image operator π:P(X×Y)P(Y)\forall_\pi: P(X \times Y) \to P(Y) takes open sets to open sets; the statement as it is, that the direct image along projection takes closed sets to closed sets, is equivalent to the other statement by De Morgan duality, but that’s where excluded middle comes in.

    • CommentRowNumber23.
    • CommentAuthortphyahoo
    • CommentTimeJul 3rd 2017
    Thank you yes, much clearer now.
    • CommentRowNumber24.
    • CommentAuthortphyahoo
    • CommentTimeJul 3rd 2017
    After a bit of grammar cleanup, Definition 2.12 now seems more obviously incoherent.

    First, we need a definition of stably closed. The colon suggests a definition, but I believe it may be an error. If it is not an error, this could be clarified by defining it on its own concept page (currently nonexistent).

    If it is an error as I suspect and "stably closed" is unrelated to the closed projection characterization, then:

    1) "stably closed" should be its own definition and perhaps its concept page should be created as well.

    2) Then definition 2.12 and 2.13 should be merged or moved up to be closer to Proposition 2.5 so that all the stuff about closed projection is in one place.
    • CommentRowNumber25.
    • CommentAuthortphyahoo
    • CommentTimeJul 3rd 2017
    I think the link to the "logic" page in

    "a logical characterisation of compactness is used in Abstract Stone Duality:"

    should be removed.
    • CommentRowNumber26.
    • CommentAuthortphyahoo
    • CommentTimeJul 3rd 2017
    It is not clear if the assumption of the ultrafilter theorem applies just to 2.7, or to 2.8 and 2.9 as well or even 2.10 and 2.11.

    I believe that Section 2.10 and 2.11 is unrelated to filters/nets but this should be made more obvious with better section numbering and breaks.

    I also believe section 2.12 is unrelated to the earlier section, but I noted this before.
    • CommentRowNumber27.
    • CommentAuthortphyahoo
    • CommentTimeJul 3rd 2017
    I think section 2.7 through 2.9 should be grouped under

    Proposition N.N. (compactness in terms of filters)

    If these are all equivalent (and ultrafilter theorem requirement applies to all) then the proposition should be along the lines of "the following three statements are equivalent."

    Similarly, section 2.10 and 2.11 should be grouped under

    Propsition N.N (compactness in terms of open sets)

    Possibly Definition 2.12 and 2.13 then get merged under proposition 2.5.

    Possibly there is also a new proposition about proper maps, that is broken out of 2.12.
    • CommentRowNumber28.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeJul 3rd 2017

    I agree, with #24, that’s what I was referring to at the end of #21.

    This needs to go to the attention of Toby and Todd, I think. The request would be: Turn these terse remarks into something a little more self-contained and inviting.

    • CommentRowNumber29.
    • CommentAuthortphyahoo
    • CommentTimeJul 3rd 2017
    I am having trouble making the above changes because of struggles with wiki markup, however, to be more explicit I think we should have something like

    Proposition 2.6. (compactness in terms of filter or net convergence)

    Let X be a topological space. Assuming the ultrafilter theorem (a weak form of the axiom of choice), then the following are equivalent:

    1 X is compact in the sense of def. 2.2.
    2-.... reformulation of definitions 2.6-2.9
    • CommentRowNumber30.
    • CommentAuthortphyahoo
    • CommentTimeJul 3rd 2017
    then

    Proposition 2.7 (compactness in terms of frames of opens)

    Let X be a topological space. Then the following are equivalent:
    1 X is compact in the sense of def. 2.2.
    2-.... reformulation of definitions 2.10 and 2.11
    • CommentRowNumber31.
    • CommentAuthortphyahoo
    • CommentTimeJul 3rd 2017
    Proposition 2.8 same thing for stably closed, if this is a stand alone concept unrelated to closed projection characterization of compactness.
    • CommentRowNumber32.
    • CommentAuthortphyahoo
    • CommentTimeJul 3rd 2017
    Proposition 2.5 can then perhaps be reforumulated as

    Let X be a topological space. Then the following are equivalent:

    1 X is compact in the sense of def. 2.2
    2 current contents of proposition 2.5
    3-... reformulation of definitions 2.12 and 2.13
    • CommentRowNumber33.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeJul 4th 2017

    Okay, I’ll begin having a look. Much of this was written (I think) by Toby quite a while ago, and his presence here has lately become more sporadic.

    Please be patient though. I am finding some of the tone harsh (e.g., “now seems more obviously incoherent” – that I find excessive), and it’s a bit of a barrage of comments now to process.

    • CommentRowNumber34.
    • CommentAuthortphyahoo
    • CommentTimeJul 4th 2017
    I'm very sorry about my tone.

    I am extremely enthusiastic about constructive math (an amateur obviously, I admit). And I admire what the nlab has accomplished collectively, as well as the individual contributors here and on the cluster of pages where I lurk. Todd / Urs / Toby: thanks for everything you've done.

    The reason I sent so many comments is I wanted to lay a breadcrumb trail for future edits to the wiki, since I was unable to edit the wiki myself to my satisfaction. It keeps cutting off the page halfway due to some formatting glitch I can't track down. And there doesn't seem to be a preview functionality.

    If there is any advice or links about editing / maintaining the wiki I will review and try to do better in the future.

    BTW, I am https://www.linkedin.com/in/thomashartman1/ just to put a face to the edits. I have been interested in constructive math for some years as a software developer doing haskell / coq for personal interest and some for work. Lurker on nlab for years I guess. I am primarily interested in constructive characterization of the reals, probably following the abstract stone duality path.
    • CommentRowNumber35.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeJul 4th 2017

    Okay, I’ve gone through and reorganized section 2 of compact space according to comments/suggestions above and my own personal knowledge. Roughly I classified the various “definitions” (now called propositions) under three headings: elementary reformulations, via convergence, and via stability properties. There is still plenty left to do: plenty of proofs which can be filled in or farmed out to other parts of the nLab, as appropriate, and still links left to be made, among other things.

    It is good that you (tphyahoo) brought your concerns to our attention, so thanks for that. I do think the article has a better shape now. The “obviously incoherent” former 2.12 is, I hope you will now see, coherent after all. I also changed the link from logic to quantification which is more precise I think.

    • CommentRowNumber36.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeJul 4th 2017

    Thanks, Todd!! That’s great.

    • CommentRowNumber37.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeJul 4th 2017

    Something seems wrong with Proposition 3.3, that the category of compact spaces has limits. (Of course compact Hausdorff spaces have limits.) The problem is that the equalizer of two maps need not be a closed subspace; that kind of thing is true if we are working with Hausdorff spaces, but not for more general spaces.

    An explicit example is where we take two maps [0,1]{0,1}[0, 1] \to \{0, 1\} where the codomain is given the indiscrete topology, where one of the maps ff has f 1(1)=[0,1/2)f^{-1}(1) = [0, 1/2), and the other is the constant map at 11. If an equalizer in CompComp existed, then hom(1,):CompSet\hom(1, -): Comp \to Set would have to preserve it, so set-theoretically it would have to be [0,1/2)[0, 1/2). The topology on [0,1/2)[0, 1/2) would have to be the same as or finer than the subspace topology in order for the equalizer map to be continuous. But if the subspace topology isn’t compact, then no finer topology would make it compact either. (Here I’m taking the contrapositive of the proposition that if (X,τ)(X, \tau) is compact and ττ\tau' \subseteq \tau is a coarser topology, then (X,τ)(X, \tau') is also compact.)

    I guess I could go in and change it to a true statement, but I’d want to know first about the situation for compact locales. Again, for compact regular locales, there’s no problem.

    • CommentRowNumber38.
    • CommentAuthorMike Shulman
    • CommentTimeJul 4th 2017

    I feel like if compact locales had limits we would know about it. Could you do something similar to your counterexample with the Sierpinski space instead of the indiscrete 2-point space?

    • CommentRowNumber39.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeJul 4th 2017

    Yes, it seems the same counterexample works with Sierpinski space, since 11 is usually taken to be the open point. (Maybe this is discussed somewhere in Stone Spaces? I don’t have my copy within easy view.) So yeah, if I think about it a little longer, maybe it will become obvious that compact frames lack coequalizers, or maybe you already see that’s true.

    • CommentRowNumber40.
    • CommentAuthortphyahoo
    • CommentTimeJul 8th 2017
    From the introduction a compact space

    "is a kind of ultimate topological expression of the general idea of a space being “closed and bounded”"

    but is it true that all compact spaces are closed with regard to some topology, or only metric spaces, or only euclidean spaces?

    Proposition 3.1 (2) has the precondition that "if the compact spaces are also closed" then the claim about inersections.

    Well, if all compact spaces are closed then this precondition can be dropped as the claim applies to all compact spaces.

    But if not all compact spaces are closed, perhaps this should be dropped from the idea section, or qualified "In metric spaces..."
    • CommentRowNumber41.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeJul 8th 2017

    That “Idea” section should be read at a very intuitive level; the language is somewhat fuzzy (I suppose by design). The author of those words should be granted some poetic license.

    Any space, compact or not, is closed in itself, so under strict interpretations some of the language of the Idea section won’t make a lot of sense. The real sense of that passage is concentrated in the words “every net has an accumulation point” (that certainly has a precise meaning), and that should be the main takeaway from what the author is trying to convey. The rest of it seems to be a simple appeal to the archetypal image we all carry around in our heads of compact sets: sets in n\mathbb{R}^n which are closed and bounded, and the author is trying to draw a connection between that intuitive conception of “closed and bounded”, based on that (finite-dimensional) picture, and the more precise mathematical conception “every net must have an accumulation point”.

    In infinite-dimensional Hilbert space (for example), “closed and bounded” do not imply compact. So that intuition comes with a (largish) grain of salt! In fact the word “bounded” isn’t quite a topological concept; it makes sense for metric spaces but it doesn’t have a meaning for general topological spaces.

    Turning to Proposition 3.1: now we’re doing mathematics, not waving intuitive wands. As it happens, compact subspaces of Hausdorff spaces are closed (and Hausdorff spaces make up the majority of spaces one encounters when first learning topology), but in general compact subsets need not be closed in the ambient space. Thus the closure hypothesis has to be inserted by hand for the proposition to work in the generality given there.

    Anyway, you may be right that the Idea section is (for some readers anyway) more confusing than enlightening. It’s hard to say, but perhaps the opening should be reconsidered.

    • CommentRowNumber42.
    • CommentAuthortphyahoo
    • CommentTimeJul 9th 2017
    "by boundedness it cannot escape, and by closure the point is in the space."

    can "it" here be replaced by "accumulation point"? I think that would be clearer.
    • CommentRowNumber43.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeJul 9th 2017

    No, the “it” here is the net (nets are generalized sequences).

    • CommentRowNumber44.
    • CommentAuthortphyahoo
    • CommentTimeJul 9th 2017
    How about

    "In typical spatial domais (such as R^n) compactness is a kind of ultimate topological expression of the general idea of a space being “closed and bounded”: .........
    • CommentRowNumber45.
    • CommentAuthortphyahoo
    • CommentTimeJul 9th 2017
    What do you think of singly linking "closed and bounded" to the heine borel theorem section (4.5) rather than linking "closed" and "bounded" separately to the two concept pages as is currently the case.

    Doesn't this give a better intuition?
    • CommentRowNumber46.
    • CommentAuthortphyahoo
    • CommentTimeJul 9th 2017
    Also it seems like many of the "Examples" (such as heine borel) fix in better in the Definitions / Characterizations section.
    • CommentRowNumber47.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeJul 9th 2017
    • (edited Jul 9th 2017)

    Re #46: no, the definitions/characterizations section is general. Heine-Borel is for a specialized set of circumstances and belongs to Examples.

    • CommentRowNumber48.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeJul 9th 2017

    Okay, I tweaked the opening paragraph just a little. I don’t agree with joining “closed” to “bounded” as in #45, but I did mention Heine-Borel. Hopefully it’s now clear that it’s more about nets and convergence than it is about being closed and bounded.

    • CommentRowNumber49.
    • CommentAuthortphyahoo
    • CommentTimeJul 9th 2017
    Much clearer.

    The verb "captures" is used twice, which makes it a little hard to concentrate on exactly what is being captured. I reworded to avoid this.
    • CommentRowNumber50.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeJul 9th 2017

    But there was no mention of compactness in the 2nd paragraph of your edit; attention was momentarily deflected away to talk about “closed and bounded”. So I had to reword again.

    Please do not remove the parentheses. They signal that a side remark is being made, which the reader can pursue if she likes, but the main focus needs to be kept on what the property is about.

    Thank you for your input, but now that some clarity has been reached, I suggest that we not spend a lot of time on what Feynman called “wordsmithing”. I’ll add that I made a change suggested by comment #37.

    • CommentRowNumber51.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeJul 9th 2017

    I took a look and ended up making some last changes myself to the Idea section:

    • made explicit that “everything” in the first sentence referred to sequences and nets

    • linked the line about not needing and ambient space for the definition with the line saying that nevertheless one does often consider compact subspaces;

    • after the claim that one likes to consider compact Hausdorff spaces, I added one reason

    • grouped the two lines about compact locales together, now at the end of the Idea-section.

    • CommentRowNumber52.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeJul 9th 2017

    Those are useful improvements, Urs – thanks.

    • CommentRowNumber53.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeJul 9th 2017

    Urs, in the idea section, did you really mean to say “paracompact” and not “locally compact”?

    • CommentRowNumber54.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeJul 9th 2017

    Argh. :-)

    Thanks. I have fixed it, and also added pointer to the proof.

    • CommentRowNumber55.
    • CommentAuthorMike Shulman
    • CommentTimeJul 12th 2018

    Mention Bishop-compactness (complete and totally bounded)

    diff, v85, current

    • CommentRowNumber56.
    • CommentAuthortphyahoo
    • CommentTimeFeb 17th 2020
    the overt space page states

    Recall that a topological space X is compact if and only if, for every other space Y and any open subspace U of X×Y, the subspace

    ∀XU={b:Y|∀a:X,(a,b)∈U}

    is open in Y.

    I think this should be stated somewhere on the compact space page, but I don't see it. Neither in any of the other related pages. IE,

    closed characterization
    compactness and stable closure

    There is a lot of material and maybe I overlooked something. If so, could someone point me the right place? If not, can it be proven?

    It seems related to closed projection characterization. On that page we have

    Theorem 1.1. A topological space X is compact if and only if for every space Y, the projection map π:Y×X→Y out of the product topological space is a closed map.

    Seems close? Anyway, can someone prove the claim above about the open product subspace U?
    • CommentRowNumber57.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeFeb 18th 2020

    It is so stated. See closed projection characterization, point 5. under Variant Proofs. It’s mentioned that this approach is in Escardo’s 2009 paper. See lemma 4.3 there.

    • CommentRowNumber58.
    • CommentAuthortphyahoo
    • CommentTimeFeb 21st 2020
    • (edited Feb 21st 2020)
    in Compactness via completeness

    "A uniform space X is compact if and only if it is complete and totally bounded."

    can this be

    "In classical mathematics, a uniform space X is compact (def 2.2) if and only if it is complete and totally bounded."

    ?
    • CommentRowNumber59.
    • CommentAuthorMike Shulman
    • CommentTimeMar 12th 2020

    Yes, that’s what’s meant. But this page is written in classical mathematics as the default, so I don’t think there’s a need to say so explicitly here, especially since the subsequent paragraph clarifies the situation in constructive mathematics.

    • CommentRowNumber60.
    • CommentAuthorDaniel Luckhardt
    • CommentTimeMar 15th 2020
    • (edited Mar 15th 2020)

    sorry, wrong thread

    • CommentRowNumber61.
    • CommentAuthorGuest
    • CommentTimeMar 22nd 2020
    In definition 2.1

    "Let (X,τ) be a topological space. Then an open cover is a set {Ui⊂X}i∈I of open subsets (i.e. (Ui⊂X)∈τ⊂P(X)) such that their union is all of X"

    This doesn't cover standard open covers of the unit interval, because it only talks about the whole space, not subspaces. Wikipedia

    https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Cover_(topology)

    has "..... Also, if Y is a subset of X, then a cover of Y is a collection of subsets of X whose union contains Y"

    I think this should be added to definition 2.1
    • CommentRowNumber62.
    • CommentAuthortphyahoo
    • CommentTimeMar 22nd 2020
    Sorry, #61 was me, tphyahoo. Forgot to sign in.
    • CommentRowNumber63.
    • CommentAuthorMike Shulman
    • CommentTimeMar 22nd 2020

    An open cover of a subset is just an open cover of that set regarded as a space with the induced topology. But we could add that as a remark afterwards.

    • CommentRowNumber64.
    • CommentAuthortphyahoo
    • CommentTimeMay 11th 2020

    missing prime in compactness for locales

    diff, v87, current

    • CommentRowNumber65.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeMay 12th 2020

    Typos like that don’t have to be mentioned.

    • CommentRowNumber66.
    • CommentAuthortphyahoo
    • CommentTimeMay 12th 2020

    Clarify if direction of prop 2.5 (locales)

    diff, v88, current

    • CommentRowNumber67.
    • CommentAuthortphyahoo
    • CommentTimeMay 12th 2020

    same as last (prop 2.5, locales, if direftion)

    diff, v88, current

    • CommentRowNumber68.
    • CommentAuthortphyahoo
    • CommentTimeMay 12th 2020
    I'm sorry the diff is a mess. Maybe it's because I copy pasted from a desktop editor. I can redo if wanted.

    I do think the changes make it more understandable.
    • CommentRowNumber69.
    • CommentAuthortphyahoo
    • CommentTimeMay 13th 2020

    give directed open cover as a definition, simplify definition of compact for locales.

    diff, v89, current

    • CommentRowNumber70.
    • CommentAuthortphyahoo
    • CommentTimeMay 13th 2020

    break off definition of directed open cover. simplify statement of compactness for locales.

    diff, v89, current

    • CommentRowNumber71.
    • CommentAuthortphyahoo
    • CommentTimeMay 13th 2020

    statement of compactness for locales

    diff, v89, current

    • CommentRowNumber72.
    • CommentAuthortphyahoo
    • CommentTimeMay 13th 2020

    statement of compactness for locales

    diff, v89, current

    • CommentRowNumber73.
    • CommentAuthorGuest
    • CommentTimeMay 13th 2020
    Is it possible to have an open cover without a direction? I don't see how.
    • CommentRowNumber74.
    • CommentAuthortphyahoo
    • CommentTimeMay 13th 2020
    73 was me.

    If every open cover is a directed open cover, then

    "Proposition 2.5. A space is compact iff every directed open cover of it has the entire space as one of its opens."

    is simply


    "Proposition 2.5. A space is compact iff every open cover of it has the entire space as one of its opens."
    • CommentRowNumber75.
    • CommentAuthortphyahoo
    • CommentTimeMay 13th 2020

    statement of compactness for locales.

    diff, v89, current

    • CommentRowNumber76.
    • CommentAuthortphyahoo
    • CommentTimeMay 13th 2020
    Looking at the diffs, it appears that there was something done to proposition 2.6. But I don't think this is the case.

    I only worked on 2.5, the first prop in compactness for locales.

    If there are any ideas why these diffs are coming in ugly, I would like to know. Again, I apologize.
    • CommentRowNumber77.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeMay 13th 2020

    I don’t think much of these are really improvements. In some cases you have been replacing other people’s words, which were fine and clear enough, with words that you would have chosen instead, such as “unioning”, a word I find grating and cacophonous outside of very informal speech.

    But let’s look at this stuff about directed open covers, where you have the paragraph with the word “Firstly”.

    Firstly, note that unions of finite opens give a direction on any open cover. This gives us the notion of a directed open cover, which is useful for locales.

    As samples of mathematical writing, both sentences of that paragraph are flawed. What one should be saying – and what I read proofs in former revisions to be saying – is that given an open cover, one can form a new cover that is directed. Not that the old cover was “given a direction”. (By the way, “give a direction” sounds clunky to my ears. I realize that the link for “directed” goes to a page titled “direction”, but I think that’s partly because of a rule we have about using noun phrases as titles. But anyway, nobody ever “gives a direction” to an open covering or to a preorder: either an open covering is directed or it isn’t. What one does is replace an open covering that may not be directed with another that is, by adding in more open sets.)

    The second sentence is flawed because “this”, whatever the antecedent is, is not “giving us a notion of” anything. “Giving a notion”, to my mind, means performing an act of conceptual analysis, as in abstracting a new concept that captures or expresses a variety of observed phenomena. “This gives us a directed open cover” is closer to what one should say, but only after fixing the first sentence.

    Really, I think it might be better to roll back to an earlier revision, and then fix whatever tiny typos needed fixing. I’m sorry to say, but I think some of the newer revisions are worsening the article. I’m not sure why you’re doing this.

    • CommentRowNumber78.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeMay 13th 2020

    (By the way, I agree that “diffs” are often hard to read. It might sometimes be easier reading different revisions in different tabs.)

    • CommentRowNumber79.
    • CommentAuthorGuest
    • CommentTimeMay 13th 2020
    okay, I reverted and made only the typo fix for U'. If I have further suggestions given your feedback I will propose here and go lighter on wiki edits.
    • CommentRowNumber80.
    • CommentAuthortphyahoo
    • CommentTimeMay 24th 2020
    In compactness for locales,
    • CommentRowNumber81.
    • CommentAuthortphyahoo
    • CommentTimeMay 24th 2020
    In compactness for locales, is the direction always defined by union of opens? IE the join semilattice of opens defined by the union operation?

    It seems likely to me to be the case, but I could imagine there might be other ways of defining a direction on the opens. And maybe these don't work for compactness..

    So if it is always upper bound of two opens is the union here for the direction, I think it would be clearer to state this explicitly.
    • CommentRowNumber82.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeMay 26th 2020
    • (edited May 26th 2020)

    It’s really very simple: a poset is directed if it is nonempty and any two elements have a common upper bound. The upper bound doesn’t have to be the union.

    I sort of wish you’d get away from this idea of “defining a direction” here. In practice, one defines a partially ordered set, and then that partially ordered set is either directed or it isn’t: there is no extra step of “defining a direction” that needs to be done. (Even “defines a partial order” sounds too elaborate, because in this context the partial order is invariably subset inclusion.) As far as any defining goes: at some point in the proof, one introduces (or defines) an open cover 𝒰\mathcal{U}' and then verifies that it is directed.

    I don’t know what is confusing you in this article, but let’s talk about it here. We have the traditional notion of compact space: every open cover has a finite subcover. The proposition in question states that compactness of a space XX is equivalent to another condition: that any directed open cover of XX has XX among its elements. I’ll call that condition D.

    Let’s just take a moment to be very explicit what all this means. First, an open cover of XX is a collection 𝒰\mathcal{U} of open subsets UXU \subseteq X whose union is XX. An open cover 𝒰\mathcal{U} is directed if, whenever one is given finitely many elements U 1,,U n𝒰U_1, \ldots, U_n \in \mathcal{U}, there is an element U𝒰U \in \mathcal{U} such that U 1U,,U nUU_1 \subseteq U, \ldots, U_n \subseteq U, in other words there exists an element U𝒰U \in \mathcal{U} that is an upper bound of the U 1,,U nU_1, \ldots, U_n with respect to subset inclusion. This UU doesn’t always have to be the actual union (i.e., the least upper bound), although it can be.

    To show that a compact space XX satisfies condition D, let 𝒰\mathcal{U} be any directed open cover. (We are not obliged to assume that 𝒰\mathcal{U} is closed under finite unions.) By compactness, 𝒰\mathcal{U} has a finite subcover, meaning there are finitely many elements U 1,U 2,,U nU_1, U_2, \ldots, U_n of 𝒰\mathcal{U} whose union (i.e. least upper bound) is XX. By the assumption that 𝒰\mathcal{U} is directed, there exists an upper bound UU of U 1,,U nU_1, \ldots, U_n belonging to 𝒰\mathcal{U}. I claim U=XU = X. First, UXU \subseteq X because by definition of open cover of XX, an element U𝒰U \in \mathcal{U} is automatically a subset of XX. But also XUX \subseteq U, because UU is an upper bound of the U 1,,U nU_1, \ldots, U_n, and the union XX which is the least upper bound is contained in the upper bound. So U=XU = X belongs to 𝒰\mathcal{U}, and thus we have verified that condition D holds.

    Now suppose that condition D holds for XX. We want to show that XX is compact. So, let 𝒰\mathcal{U} be any open cover of XX; we want to show that under condition D, there exists finitely many U 1,,U n𝒰U_1, \ldots, U_n \in \mathcal{U} whose union is XX. Of course we can’t apply condition D directly to 𝒰\mathcal{U} because 𝒰\mathcal{U}, regarded as being partially ordered by subset inclusion, might not be directed. But if we introduce a new open cover 𝒰\mathcal{U}' whose elements are precisely the possible finite unions of elements of 𝒰\mathcal{U}, then 𝒰\mathcal{U}' is directed. (Of course this should be proven. So, suppose given elements V 1,,V nV_1, \ldots, V_n of 𝒰\mathcal{U}'. According to how 𝒰\mathcal{U}' was defined, each V iV_i is a finite union U i,1U i,k iU_{i, 1} \cup \ldots \cup U_{i, k_i} of elements of 𝒰\mathcal{U}. But then V=V 1V n= i=1 n j=1 k iU i,jV = V_1 \cup \ldots \cup V_n = \bigcup_{i=1}^n \bigcup_{j=1}^{k_i} U_{i, j}, being a union of finitely many elements of 𝒰\mathcal{U}, belongs to 𝒰\mathcal{U}'. This VV is an upper bound of V 1,,V nV_1, \ldots, V_n.) Since 𝒰\mathcal{U}' is directed and since condition D holds, we have that X𝒰X \in \mathcal{U}'. But then by definition of 𝒰\mathcal{U}', the set XX is a union of finitely many elements U 1,,U nU_1, \ldots, U_n of 𝒰\mathcal{U}. This completes the proof.

    • CommentRowNumber83.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeMay 26th 2020

    By the way, I don’t mean to sound overly harsh in my last comment. In view of the way the article direction is written, it’s not necessarily wrong to speak of “defining a direction” (on a set) – it’s just that in this context, it sounds really weird and overly elaborate to write that way. It would be more appropriate to write that way if one started with a set SS and was contemplating, among the infinitely many ways in which SS could carry a structure of directed partial order, which one of them one wishes to single out as the topic of discussion. But in the present discussion, there’s really no choice in the matter: the only relevant partial ordering is given by subset inclusion (or the given partial order if one is starting with a frame or subsets of a frame), and it’s only a question of whether the poset under discussion is directed or not.

    So much so that if a reader encounters the phrase “define a direction by” in the article compact space, it would be natural to wonder if the author was confused or didn’t quite understand what they were talking about.

    • CommentRowNumber84.
    • CommentAuthorMike Shulman
    • CommentTimeMay 27th 2020

    I don’t know if this is what tphyahoo has in mind, but in constructive mathematics one might want the “directedness” of a directed poset to be given by a function assigning a particular upper bound to any two elements, since in the absence of choice having such a thing is a stronger assumption than the mere existence of upper bounds. However, in a join-semilattice there is always a function that selects the least upper bound, since those are uniquely defined.

    • CommentRowNumber85.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeMay 27th 2020

    Right, that would be a more structural (actually, algebraic over posets) notion of direction where the phrase “define a direction” would make sense. It seems that direction (written largely by Toby, I think) was not written with this possibility in mind – and offhand, it strikes me as a superfluous consideration for the compact space article.

    • CommentRowNumber86.
    • CommentAuthorMike Shulman
    • CommentTimeMay 27th 2020

    Yes, the distinction isn’t relevant for compactness.

  1. adding a few sentences on compact topological spaces vs compact convergence spaces in constructive mathematics in section “Compactness via convergence”. In particular, the failure of the equivalence of the definitions in constructive mathematics suggests that this article needs to be split up into “compact topological space” and “compact convergence space”, because that compact topological spaces (in the sense of open covers and finite subcovers) are compact convergence spaces (in the sense of nets and convergent subnets) implies excluded middle.

    Anonymous

    diff, v93, current

    • CommentRowNumber88.
    • CommentAuthorDmitri Pavlov
    • CommentTimeJun 30th 2023

    Added:

    History

    Compact spaces were introduced (under the name of “bicompact spaces”) by Paul Alexandroff and Paul Urysohn around 1924, see the 92nd volume of Mathematische Annalen, especially AU.

    diff, v97, current