Not signed in (Sign In)

Not signed in

Want to take part in these discussions? Sign in if you have an account, or apply for one below

  • Sign in using OpenID

Discussion Tag Cloud

Vanilla 1.1.10 is a product of Lussumo. More Information: Documentation, Community Support.

Welcome to nForum
If you want to take part in these discussions either sign in now (if you have an account), apply for one now (if you don't).
    • CommentRowNumber1.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeSep 27th 2012

    In the entry spacetime there used to be a subsection on the “hole argument”. It started out with Tim van Beek recalling the “hole paradox” and then continuing with me adding a lengthy discussion, with the result being an organizational mess as far as the poor entry that hosted it was concerned.

    I have now moved that material into its own entry hole paradox, gave it a coherent and concise (I hope) idea-section, and cross-linked with general covariance.

    The section “The hole argument” there is what Tim had originally written, I think, whereas the section Discussion is what I had added back then.

    I am not claiming that that “discussion” of mine is necessarily particular well formulated, but I claim that it gets to the point.

    Looking around I see that one finds the weirdest things being said about the “hole paradox”. For instance the first sentence this article here.

    I am not proposing that we get into this. All I wanted to achieve here is to clean up the poor entry spacetime.

    • CommentRowNumber2.
    • CommentAuthorMike Shulman
    • CommentTimeMar 12th 2015

    After a brief discussion on nlab-talk, I have replaced the beginning of the “Discussion” section of hole argument with some paragraphs that I feel bring out the nPOV point more explicitly. I wanted to incorporate more of the previous version, but I just wasn’t able to see how to fit it together (in particular, I didn’t really understand the purpose of the discussion of probes and diffeological spaces). Feel free to edit further.

    • CommentRowNumber3.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeMar 12th 2015
    Thanks, that's good.
    • CommentRowNumber4.
    • CommentAuthorspitters
    • CommentTimeMay 8th 2015
    • (edited May 8th 2015)

    While looking for something else I came across this (Fibered Manifolds, Natural Bundles, Structured Sets, G-Sets). A categorical treatment of the hole argument entitled . Currently, the page is a bit low on references, but I don’t have the time to pursue it right now. I hope this will be useful later and not add to the noise.

    • CommentRowNumber5.
    • CommentAuthorDavid_Corfield
    • CommentTimeSep 26th 2019

    Added to references

    diff, v4, current

    • CommentRowNumber6.
    • CommentAuthorMike Shulman
    • CommentTimeSep 28th 2019

    I want to read that! But it’s paywalled, can anyone send me a copy?

    • CommentRowNumber7.
    • CommentAuthorUlrik
    • CommentTimeSep 28th 2019
    • (edited Sep 28th 2019)

    Check your mail, Mike.

    I’m confused about Dougherty’s proposed definition of generally covariant Lorentzian manifolds, though. He says that we should fix a notion of hole diffeomorphism (a property a diffeomorphism can have). To make sense of this, I think we need a family of hole structures: HoleStr:MfldSetHoleStr : Mfld \to Set, taking values in inhabited sets, such that we can define HoleMfld:= M:MfldHoleStr(M)HoleMfld := \sum_{M : Mfld} HoleStr(M), and the projection HoleMfldMfldHoleMfld \to Mfld becomes a 00-truncated, 1-1-connected map of groupoids.

    I quote here his Definition 1:

    A generally covariant Lorentzian metric on a manifold MM is specified by a Lorentzian metric gg, and an equality g=gg = g' of generally covariant Lorentzian metrics on M is a hole diffeomorphism ψ:MM\psi : M \to M such that ψ *(g)=g\psi_*(g)=g'. A generally covariant Lorentzian manifold is a pair (M,g)(M, g) of a smooth manifold MM and a generally covariant Lorentzian metric gg on MM. Thus, an equality (M,g)=(M,g)(M, g) = (M' , g') of generally covariant Lorentzian manifolds is a pair (φ,ψ)(\varphi, \psi) of a diffeomorphism φ:MM\varphi : M \to M' and a hole diffeomorphism ψ:MM\psi : M' \to M' such that ψ *(φ *(g))=g\psi_*(\varphi_*(g)) = g'.

    That can’t be right, because we need a hole structure ss on MM to even talk about hole diffeomorphisms (namely those that preserve ss). So I think the definition of generally covariant Lorentzian metrics should be a map gcLorMet:HoleMfldGpdgcLorMet : HoleMfld \to Gpd that takes (M,s)(M,s) to the Rezk completion of the strict groupoid whose objects are Lorentzian metrics gg and whose morphisms are as above.

    Is that right, or am I confused? What does that mean more concretely? And what are candidates for the type of hole structures? (Dougherty doesn’t discuss this.) Is there a better description of the type of generally covariant Lorentzian manifolds as a 11-type?

    • CommentRowNumber8.
    • CommentAuthorDavidRoberts
    • CommentTimeSep 28th 2019
    • (edited Sep 28th 2019)

    Heh, have two. You beat me to posting by seconds, Ulrik.

    • CommentRowNumber9.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeSep 28th 2019
    • (edited Sep 28th 2019)

    The definition that Ulrik kindly quotes for us in #7 seems strange even if fixed to make technical sense:

    1) The term “generally covariant Lorentzian metric” is weird in itself. I imagine people might say this in informal chat for emphasis, but only to mean plain “Lorentzian metric”.

    2) What really seems to be meant in the definition is what should be termed “Lorentzian manifold equipped with a fixed isometry to a fixed Lorentzian manifold”.

    • CommentRowNumber10.
    • CommentAuthorMike Shulman
    • CommentTimeSep 28th 2019

    Thanks, Ulrik and David.

    I’m happy to see this direction being explored more explicitly, but I have to say I think this paper goes off the rails even earlier than that. On page 12 we read

    An equality of models in HoTT is an isometry of Lorentzian manifolds in the category-theoretic semantics. A pair of models that agree on some region consists of two triples (M,g,S)(M, g, S) and (M,g,S)(M' , g' , S')—where (M,g)(M, g) and (M,g)(M', g') are Lorentzian manifolds and SS and SS' are submanifolds of MM and MM', respectively—along with a diffeomorphism φ:MM\varphi : M \to M' such that φ(S)=S\varphi(S) = S' and φ *(g)=g\varphi_\ast(g) = g' when restricted to SS'.

    This already seems wrong to me. I would say that a pair of models that agree on some region consists of two such triples and an isometry (S,g| S)(S,g| S)(S,g|_S) \cong (S',g'|_{S'}). Why would the notion of two models that “agree on some region” include any data at all comparing the two models outside that region? I think this mistake is what leads to all his complications. With the correct notion of “two models that agree on some region”, we can answer the determinism question quite simply by saying that indeed, two models that agree on a sufficiently large region must also agree outside that region, in the sense that the given isometry can be extended (uniquely) to an isometry (M,g)(M,g)(M,g)\cong (M',g').

    • CommentRowNumber11.
    • CommentAuthorMike Shulman
    • CommentTimeSep 28th 2019

    Of course, whether that last claim of determinism is true is a mathematical theorem that one would have to prove about GR: is the topology of spacetime inside a hole determined by the outside of the hole as well as the metric on it? I would have assumed that it had already been done, but if as this paper suggests it isn’t even clear to people what the right way to say “GR is deterministic” is, then maybe not. Anyone know?

    • CommentRowNumber12.
    • CommentAuthorDavid_Corfield
    • CommentTimeSep 29th 2019

    Added a more explicit link to the HoTT treatment at general covariance.

    diff, v5, current