Want to take part in these discussions? Sign in if you have an account, or apply for one below
Vanilla 1.1.10 is a product of Lussumo. More Information: Documentation, Community Support.
1 to 14 of 14
I was reading MacLane (like a good student) and when I saw the diagram for a universal arrow, it made me think of natural transformations.
It looked like we could describe a comma category as a natural transformation , where is a constant functor.
If so, then the universal arrow, i.e. initial object of the comma category, would be like the “initial component” of a natural transformation.
Does that make any sense?
Then, if I push my luck, it looks like if has an initial object , then the component is a universal arrow. Is that correct?
I’m in a bit of a rush, so I don’t have time to write more, but note that, as described at comma category, the category is the universal category with a transformation from (the constant functor) to , where the arrows out of are the projections. So certainly depends on this transformation, but it’s also universal among squares-with-a-transformation-in over the cospan .
To answer one question: a category isn’t a transformation, so you can’t describe a comma category like that. But as Finn already noted, there is a connection. If is the functor that sends an object to , then a natural transformation is essentially the same thing as a section of . For, such a section would have to take each object to some object of the form , where the first component would be your component , and would take each morphism to the pair
where the triangle must commute by definition of . The commutativity means the are components of a natural transformation .
(I see you’re wrapping your head around limits. That’s good!)
As for #2: If is initial in , there’s a universal cone whose component at an object of is the arrow , where is the unique arrow to . Universality means that given any cone , there’s a unique such that is the composite
and this is exactly , as you surmise.
(I see you’re wrapping your head around limits. That’s good!)
Well, I made a little progress with Yoneda lemma and went back to Dugger hoping I’d get to the point I understand enough about sheaves so that I could get back to Baez-Hoffnung, but then realized that Dugger is STILL a bit over my head, so fell back to MacLane to study the basics again. I’m feeling things are less mysterious this time around, but it is not easy to penetrate my thick skull.
While I was reading the section in MacLane on universal arrows, the diagram
looked like the components of a natural transformation
Hence my question. So you’re giving me a little too much credit, but I’m trying and making some progress :)
looked like the components of a natural transformation
Yes, indeedy. Exactly right.
So, there’s a running dictionary, that a cone with vertex is the exact same thing as a natural transformation . And a morphism of cones from to is a map so that all the relevant triangles
commute for all objects in the domain of , but that just translates to saying
commutes as a diagram of natural transformations.
(A next step would be to understand a universal cone in terms of a representing object, but please carry on.)
I’ll just add to Todd’s explanation, in case you hadn’t spotted it, that the correspondence between your and his section of (i.e. ) is precisely the universal property of the comma category:
That’s a bit messy, but your lives in the square ’behind’ the comma square. Then is unique making the rhombuses commute: the top one commutes trivially, because both morphisms land in the terminal object, and the left one says exactly that is a section of .
Ha ha – that was exactly the diagram I had in mind, but I knew I wouldn’t be able to render it nicely!
I knew it was the one you were thinking of, but for my part I thought ’better drawn badly than not drawn at all.’ :)
Thanks for the help, but just so you know, any diagram more complicated than a component of a natural transformation makes me nervous :)
It will take some time to try to parse what you’ve said, but I’ll try (when I get a chance).
Quick sanity check.
In Finn’s comment #7, the top path is the constant functor if we label . Right? (Deja vu: I think I wanted to use the notation for the constant functor at one point for this very reason.)
The bottom path is just .
Ok. I’m pretty sure I got that, but it felt good to say it out loud :)
So is the limit of that cospan in , i.e. pullback. Right?
Ok. So we have the natural transformation and the other one .
So there is a 3-dimensional thingie mobob relating this two natural transformations. What is that thingie called? (Sorry to get so technical on you :))
Not quite. You’re right about the top and bottom paths, though.
There is a cospan . The category is not the pullback but the comma object over this. The pullback would be the universal commuting square over the cospan, whereas the comma object is the universal square containing a transformation. The transformation is the transformation in the universal (comma) sqaure.
Now you also have the transformation , which also lives in a square over the cospan given by and . So by the universality of the comma object , there is a unique morphism (functor) that makes the rhombuses commute. In particular, there’s nothing 3-dimensional going on.
The crappiness of my diagram is certainly no help. What I was trying to draw was two squares-with-transformations-in over the same cospan, together with a morphism between the objects (categories) in the top left corners of the square.
Does that help?
The pullback would be the universal commuting square over the cospan, whereas the comma object is the universal square containing a transformation.
That is interesting. Is there any way this is an incarnation of a 2-limit or something? Not that I’d have much of a chance of understanding that.
In particular, there’s nothing 3-dimensional going on.
Well, a square with a natural transformation is 2-dimensional, so we have two solid squares connected by a morphism and everything in sight commutes, so I still think there is something 3-dimensional going on, but maybe that is semantics :)
For example, that section morphism looks like some component of some 3-morphism. Or something…
The crappiness of my diagram is certainly no help.
Like you said, any diagram is better than no diagram :) I think the first time I looked at it, I thought and were objects. Once I knew they were labeling the morphisms, it made more sense :)
Does that help?
Yes, it does. Thanks! :)
Gah! I typed out a reply, then accidentally hit ’Back’ and lost it all >:(
Is there any way this is an incarnation of a 2-limit or something?
Yes! In fact it’s a strict 2-limit, which is a Cat-weighted limit.
I still think there is something 3-dimensional going on, but maybe that is semantics :)
Certainly, the diagram is quite pleasing when thought of as 3-dimensional, but what I meant was that there are no 3-cells around. The only 3-morphisms I can think of here are the modifications in 2-Cat, but their components are 2-cells.
1 to 14 of 14