Processing math: 100%
Not signed in (Sign In)

Not signed in

Want to take part in these discussions? Sign in if you have an account, or apply for one below

  • Sign in using OpenID

Discussion Tag Cloud

Vanilla 1.1.10 is a product of Lussumo. More Information: Documentation, Community Support.

Welcome to nForum
If you want to take part in these discussions either sign in now (if you have an account), apply for one now (if you don't).
    • CommentRowNumber1.
    • CommentAuthordomenico_fiorenza
    • CommentTimeDec 12th 2010
    • (edited Dec 12th 2010)

    Here is where I’ll blog my redaing of Topological Quantum Field Theories from Compact Lie Groups

    day 1. quickly read the intro and gone directly to section1. main statement there is proposition 1.2, identifying H2(BG,) with the group of abelian characters Hom(G,U(1)). in nLab we have a nice understanding of this identification as follows: the set of abelian characters is the set of cocycles c:BGBU(1), and the above identification follows by the long fibration sequence of oo-Lie groupoids

    BBBU(1)B()B2

    The description of the 01 tqft associated with c:BGBU(1) is given explicitely. Apparently it can be interpreted as follows: the vector space F(pt) associated to a point is the space of sections of the line bundle on the groupoid BG induced by the cocycle c (this space of sections will be 1- or 0-dimensional depending whether c is the trivial cocycle or not). The complex number F(S1) associated to S1 is the dimension of this vector space. This can be seen as the integral over [S1,BG] of the morphism [S1,BG][S1,BU(1)]U(1) induced by c.

    That F(S1) is related this way to the space of maps from S1 to BG and to the cocycle c seems to be what is really crucial here. Yet in section 1 no deep reason for this being “the right answer” is given at this level and it is only remarked that the above described interpretation of dimF(S1) is possible.

    • CommentRowNumber2.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeDec 13th 2010
    • (edited Dec 13th 2010)

    Thanks, for starting this, Domenico.

    The complex number F(S1) associated to S1 is the dimension of this vector space. This can be seen as the integral over [S1,BG] of the morphism [S1,BG][S1,BU(1)]U(1) induced by c.

    We said the following before elsewhere, but let’s recall it:

    if we think of vector spaces and linear algebra along the lines of integral transforms on sheaves, then the morphism

    [S1,BG]exp(S())[S1,BU(1)]U(1)

    is the path integral over the action, when regarded as an object in

    H/U(1),

    where H=Grpd here: we have an -groupoid over U(1) and under groupoid-cardinality in this is the Haar measure-weighted path integral over exp(S()).

    Also just for the record, so that we get set up again for this discussion, this argument corresponds to theorem 6, page 16 of Simon Willerton’s article.

    • CommentRowNumber3.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeDec 13th 2010
    • (edited Dec 13th 2010)

    An analogous statement should holds for the space assigned to the point:

    The identification H/BGPSh(BG) goes via the (,1)-Grothendieck construction. So up to equivalence every element in the over -category is given by a fibration ψ:ΨBG. This is like a flat bundle of -groupoids over BG: an -groupoid fiber over the point and then autoequivalences for each gG.

    So the action functional again gives us a composite

    Ψ[pt,BG]exp(S())[pt,BU(1)]BU(1)ρVect

    and we ought to be able to interpret this under a cardinality operation as a vector space (by passing to (co)invariants).

    So there should be this picture here: for ΣinΣΣout we have

    [Σin,BG][Σ,BG][Σout,BG][Σin,BU(1)][Σ,BU(1)][Σout,BU(1)][Σin,Vect][Σ,Vect][Σout,Vect]

    and we should be pull-pushing through this int the corresponding over -toposes.

    • CommentRowNumber4.
    • CommentAuthordomenico_fiorenza
    • CommentTimeDec 13th 2010
    • (edited Dec 14th 2010)

    Hi Urs,

    thanks for joining this! :)

    We said the following before elsewhere, but let’s recall it

    yes, recalling that here is a very good idea, thanks.

    and now… day 2 :)

    I’ve skipped to Section 3 to see how the 0-1 tqft case is handled by the general theory. adapting for n=1 the beginning of Section 3, the starting point is the existence of the BunG functor BunG:BordSO1Fam1, which maps a manifold M to the groupoid of principal G-bundles oner M (G is a finite group here). So this is nothing but the functor MH(M,BG) or, in the internal version M[M,BG].

    Next, fixing Vect to be the symmetric monoidal category 𝒞 involved, the classical theory is given by a lift I:BordSO1Fam1(Vect) of BunG.Here, objects in Fam1(Vect) are objects in Fam1, i.e., finite groupoids, with a morphism to Vect; morphisms are branes

    ZXYVect

    In the case of a 0-1 tqft out of a cocycle c:BGBU(1) the functor I is defined by I(pt+)={BGVect} where the morphism to Vect is induced by c and by the standard representation of U(1). This definition of I therefore relies on the cobordism hypotesis in the version given by Theorem 2.1 in the paper: since SO(1) is the trivial group, giving I:BordSO1Fam1(Vect) is the same thing that giving a fully dualizable object in Fam1(Vect).

    This leaves it completely implicit what is I on 1-manifolds, which is not completely satisfying. I’ll come back to this later.

  1. Sill on the 0-1 tqft case. So far we have explicitly described only I(pt+). The definition of I(pt+) forces I(pt) to be the representation of G dual of the one associated with pt+. So, explicitely, gφ=c(g)1φ, for φ:. Then I([0,1]) as a cobordism from p+ to p+ is the identity of I(p+) as a representation of G; similarly, I([0,1]) as a cobordism between p+p and is the canonical pairing I(p)I(p+) and I([0,1]) as a cobordism between and p+p is the copairing I(p+)I(p). Note that here we are using the fact that I() is the trivial 1-dimensional representation of G, which is forced by the fact that I() has to be the unit in the symmetric monoidal category of representations of finite groupoids. Note that I maps a 1-manifold with boundary to a morphism between functors to Vect rather than to a functor from a groupoid to Vect. This is obvious, since a 1-manifold is a 1-morphism in BordSO1 and so it has to be mapped to a 1-morphism in Fam1(Vect).

    Next we come to I(S1). Since I lifts BunG, I(S1), this has I(S1) has to be a functor [S1,BG]0Vect=. that is I(S1) has to be a class function on G. This is is agreement with the brane interpretation of morphisms: from the cospan S1 we get the span of groupoids *[S1,BG]*, and branes with this roof over Vect are naturally identified with class functions on G. and with the given data there is no better candidate for this class function than the cocycle c itself, seen as a function c:GU(1). With this choice,

    F(S1)=Sum0(I(S1))=1|G|gGc(g)

    in accordance with the formula on page 4 of the paper.

    Note that the fact that I maps S1 to a functor G//G0Vect has a simple and natural interpretation: since S1 is a cobordism from the empty manifold to itself, I(S1) has to be a functor taking values in the space of morphisms of the unit of 1Vect.

  2. I’m not satisfied with the ad hoc definition of [S1,BG]0Vect. I’d like this to be [S1,BG][S1,Vect], induced by BGVect, but I’m presently unable to give a rigorous meaning to [S1,Vect]. Yet, I’m convinced precisely this is the key of the whole construction.

    • CommentRowNumber7.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeDec 14th 2010

    but I’m presently unable to give a rigorous meaning to [S1,Vect].

    The canonical interpretation would be as the functor category (or rather its core fr the purposes here) from the groupoid incarnation of S1 to Vect. That is the groupoid whose objects are linear endomorphisms on a vector space, and whose morphisms are conjugations by invertible linear maps.

    What is important is, I think, that we regard Vect as a pointed category, with point the ground field k regarded as a vector space over itself. The component of core(Func(S1,Vect)) on this component is k//k× (since kEndk(k)). So its 0-truncation is indeed k.

  3. Hi Urs,

    the functor category interpretation works extremely well! and we do not need to regard Vect as a pointed category nor to restrict to the core. Indeed, if BGVect is the functor induced by c composed with the standard representation of U(1), then the induced fnctor [S1,BG][S1,Vect] between functor categories maps the object (*,g) to the object (,c(g)) and the morphism h:(*,g)(*,h1gh) to the morphism c(h):(,c(g))(,c(h)1c(g)c(h)) (where I left the conjugation explicit to have a form which is still valid for higher dimensional representations of G).

    So this part is ok, and to finally land in we just need to take the trace, Tr:[S1,Vect].

    • CommentRowNumber9.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeDec 15th 2010

    All right! :-)

    we just need to take the trace

    Hopefully that will be said more intrinsically. At least for the 1-dimensional case, this step is 0-truncation of [S1,Vect].

  4. Hopefully that will be said more intrinsically.

    Yes, having a good intrinsic understanding of what is Tr:[S1,Vect] seems to be a crucial point here. I don’t clearly see this as the truncation morphism [S1,Vect]τ0[S1,Vect] unless “the 1-dimensional case” refers to the dimension of the vector space V in the object (V,φ) of [S1,Vect].

    Apart this, I was thinking that for K a 1-dimensional manifold (with boundary), the functor category [K,Vect] is a categorical verison of (a particular case of) the labelled diagrams appearing in Joyal-Street-Reshetikhin-Turaev graphical calculus for morphisms. So it seems that on the one hand we have a sort of “decorated cobordism” BordSO1(Vect) equipped with a natural morphism to Vect given by the graphical calculus, and on the other we have the cocycle c inducing BordSO1(BG)BordSO1(Vect). The composition of these is BordSO1(BG)Vect and pushing forward to the point gives the tqft BordSO1Vect.

    So the crucial step seems to understand [K,nVect]nVect in arbitrary dimension.

  5. The morphism BordSO1(Vect)Vect should be completely natural and have the following interpretation: BordSO1(Vect) is the free symmetric monoidal category with duals generated by Vect; hence, for any symmetric monoidal category with duals 𝒞 and any functor F:Vect𝒞, is induced a duality preserving symmetric monoidal functor Z:BordSO1(Vect)𝒞 extending F.

    This appears to be a simple repharsing of Joyal-Street-Reshetikhin-Turaev diagrammatics, and suggests the following general statement: BordSOn() is the adjoint of the inclusion {symmetric monoidal (,n)-categories with duals}{(,n)-categories}

    Given an arbitrary symmetric monoidal (,n)-category 𝒞, I expect that the full subcategory fd(𝒞) on fully dualizable objects is a symmetric monoidal (,n)-category with duals, so the conjectured adjuction above would in paticular give an equivalence between duality preserving symmetric monoidal functors BordSOn(*)fd(𝒞)𝒞 and objects in fd(𝒞), i.e., the cobordism hypothesis in its original formulation.

    Coming back to the BGBU(1) example, the above seems to say that a symmetric monoidal morphism BordSO1(BG)Vect is completely determined (or better its homotopy class is) by the morphism BGVect induced by the cocycle c:BGBU(1). Next the problem of pushing this forward to a symmetric monoidal morphism BordSO1Vect seems to be reduced to the problem of pushing forward BGVect along BG*. This is a particular case of the problem of pushing forward a morphism XVect along X*, where X is any garoupioid, and this can in turn be conveniently expressed in terms of left or right Kan extensions. This precisely transates the limit or colimit formulation of Sum1 in the paper.

  6. according to this MO answer, the left adjoint point of view seems to be correct. I’ll be presently not working on the details of this, but rather will try to read the constructions in Freed-Hopkins-Lurie-Teleman in the light of it. The n=1 case sketched above seems to say that this point of view is promising.

    • CommentRowNumber13.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeDec 18th 2010

    I expect that the full subcategory fd(𝒞) on fully dualizable objects is a symmetric monoidal (,n)-category with duals

    Yes, that’s part of claim 2.3.19 of Classification of TFTs . I have finally started an entry symmetric monoidal (infinity,n)-category and recorded that statement there.

    • CommentRowNumber14.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeDec 18th 2010
    • (edited Dec 18th 2010)

    Hi Domenico,

    I had been distracted by some other things and seem to have lost you a bit. Could you say again what you said before about BordSOn(Vect)? I understand that you say you want to think of this as denoting the free “with dual”ization of Vect, but I am not sure if I see why and how.

    (I do remember that before we discussed elsewhere that Bord(X) should be the free symmetric-monoidalization of Π(X) in some sense.)

    Also you write the cocycle c:BGVect induces BordSOn(BG)BordSOn(Vect). But by “BordSOn(BG)” we used to denote the n-category of cobordisms equipped with maps to BG. Is that still what you ,mean?

    Sorry for not following, but if you could just restate in a paragraph what you are after now, that might help.

    • CommentRowNumber15.
    • CommentAuthordomenico_fiorenza
    • CommentTimeDec 18th 2010
    • (edited Dec 18th 2010)

    Hi Urs,

    let me use two distinct notations here not to make things foggier than they deserve. On the one side we should have a left adjoint to the inclusion of symmetric monoidal (,n)-categories with duals into (infy,n)-categories. Let us denote this by Freen. On the other side we have a notion of 𝒞-decorated bordism, that is, precisely, n-cobordism with maps to 𝒞, something we could denote by BordSOn(𝒞) or more explicitly [BordSOn,𝒞].

    The arguments in the final part of Classification of TQFTs seem to suggest an equivalence Freen(𝒞)BordSOn(𝒞). Details of this are still unclear to me, except in the n=1 case where it is a familiar statement from Joyal-Street-Reshetikhin-Turaev. Assuming the statement is true, then by definition of adjointness we have, for any symmetric monoidal (,n)-category with duals 𝒞, a natural morphism BordSOn(𝒞)𝒞. What I’m saying is that (again at least in the n=1 case where I’ve gone through the details) this nicely gives the construction in TQFTs from compact Lie groups.

    Namely, c:BGVect induces BordSO1(BG)BordSO1(Vect). Since Vect is a symmetric monoidal category with duals (I’m assuming Vect is denoting the category of finite dimensional vector spaces), then we have the natural symmetric monoidal duality preserving morphism BordSO1(Vect)Vect induced by the universal property of BordSO1, and so we end up with a symmetric monoidal morphism BordSO1(BG)Vect. Now to end up witha tqft we are left with the task of pushing this forward along BG*. Here the idea is: consider the Kan extension of c:BGVect along BG*, and apply to the homotopy commutative diagram you obtatin the hom-functor [BordSO1,]. This, together with the natural morphism BordSO1(Vect)Vect gives the diagram

    BordSO1(BG)BordSO1(Vect)VectBordSO1(*)

    whose “lower profile” should be the seeked tqft.

    edit: is the lower profile the Kan extension

    BordSO1(BG)VectBordSO1(*)

    ?

  7. the n=2 case seems to go straightforwardly along these lines: a cocylce c:BGB2U(1) induces a morphism BG2Vect, where 2Vect is the 2-category whose objects are algebras and whose morphisms are bimodules (this 2-category is denoted Alg in FHLT). The defining representation B2U(1)2Vect maps the unique object of B2U(1) to the algebra , the unique 1-morphism of B2U(1) to vector space (as a (,)-bimodule), and the element xU(1) (as a 2-morphism in B2U(1)) to the element xU(1)End(). the Kan extension of BG2Vect along BG* is the twisted group algebra of G (this is example 3.14 in FHLT).

    • CommentRowNumber17.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeDec 19th 2010
    • (edited Dec 19th 2010)

    Hi Domenico,

    sorry to be slowing things down, but I have more questions about what precisely you are thinking of now. Of course I recognize plenty of ideas here, but to make progress I feel I need better grip on where you are thinking of precise statements and where you are sketching how the story ought to run.

    let me use two distinct notations here not to make things foggier than they deserve. On the one side we should have a left adjoint to the inclusion of symmetric monoidal (,n)-categories with duals into (infy,n)-categories. Let us denote this by Freen. On the other side we have a notion of 𝒞-decorated bordism, that is, precisely, n-cobordism with maps to 𝒞,

    What kind of map from a cobordism Σ to 𝒞 are you thinking of here? Do you still map the groupoid Π(Σ) to 𝒞?

    something we could denote by BordSOn(𝒞) or more explicitly [BordSOn,𝒞].

    The latter notation has an evident interpretation as the n-category of (symmetric monoidal) n-functors Bordn𝒞 (i.e. an extended nd-TFT with values in 𝒞). But I don’t think that that’s what you mean. I’d think it takes a bit more discussion to say what one might mean here. But maybe I am missing something.

    except in the n=1 case where it is a familiar statement from Joyal-Street-Reshetikhin-Turaev

    There is a famous “Reshitikhin-Turaev construction” for n=3 and 𝒞 a modular tensor category. That’s not what you mean, though?

    the n=2 case seems to go straightforwardly along these lines: a cocylce c:BGB2U(1) induces a morphism BG2Vect, where 2Vect is the 2-category whose objects are algebras and whose morphisms are bimodules (this 2-category is denoted Alg in FHLT). The defining representation B2U(1)2Vect maps the unique object of B2U(1) to the algebra , the unique 1-morphism of B2U(1) to vector space (as a (,)-bimodule), and the element xU(1) (as a 2-morphism in B2U(1)) to the element xU(1)End(). the Kan extension of BG2Vect along BG* is the twisted group algebra of G (this is example 3.14 in FHLT).

    Yes, over a point, the quantization construction is a plain colimit. When extending this to all cobordisms, things tend to get trickier.

    Let me see…

    • CommentRowNumber18.
    • CommentAuthordomenico_fiorenza
    • CommentTimeDec 19th 2010
    • (edited Dec 19th 2010)

    Hi Urs,

    no need to apologize: I see what I’m writing here is really foggy. What I’m trying to fix is an essential version of the constructions in FHLT: my impression there is that in many occasions they describe some object coming out of nowhere as the "right" object, and only after they give a simple general recipe which would have produced that specific object. This is particularly evident in the case of the tensor category defined in section 4 of FHLT: the general argument of the paper suggest that should arise very simply as the colimit of the functor BG3Vect induced by the cocycle c:BGB3U(1), and by the defining representation B3U(1)3Vect mapping the unique object of B3U(1) to the tensor category of finite dimensional vector spaces over . Yet, this seems not to be stated explicitely in the paper.

    So, for how trivial it is, I’m now going to spend some time to convince myself that what I’ve just written is correct :)

    What kind of map from a cobordism Σ to 𝒞 are you thinking of here? Do you still map the groupoid Π(Σ) to 𝒞?

    Yes, probably that’s the correct way of looking at what I’m at the moment thinking in more naive terms: namely, I’m presently thinking in terms of functors from a triangulation of Σ to 𝒞. Extremely rough, as you see. I guess you are right and Π(Σ) is the right object to be considered.

    something we could denote by BordSOn(𝒞) or more explicitly [BordSOn,𝒞].

    You are right, teh second notation is absolutely confusing. What I had in mind is the following: BordSOn(𝒞) maps a triangulated manifold Σ to the [Σ,𝒞]. So, adoping the Π(Σ) point of view (which I’m conviced should be the correct one), this should be

    BordSOn(𝒞):Σ[Π(Σ),𝒞]

    at least as a first approximation.

    There is a famous "Reshitikhin-Turaev construction" for n=3 and 𝒞 a modular tensor category. That’s not what you mean, though?

    I mean the following: given an arbitrary category 𝒞, one can consider the category whose objects are finite sequences of objects of 𝒞 (each one equipped with a +/ sign), and whose morphisms are oriented links between these sequences, with strands decorated by morphisms in 𝒞. Juxtaposition of links and the "obvious" braiding makes this a symmetric monoidal category, and if i’m not wrong this should be the free symmetric monoidal category generated by 𝒞. I’m not sure of the source for this construction, but I think I’ve learned it from works of Joyal-Street and Reshetikhin-Turaev.

    Yes, over a point, the quantization construction is a plain colimit. When extending this to all cobordisms, things tend to get trickier.

    Absolutely. But I’m confident we can get to the point where tricks disappear and things become completely natural. Having a good understandng of what happens over the point is a good beginning..

    • CommentRowNumber19.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeDec 20th 2010
    • (edited Dec 20th 2010)

    this should be […]

    Yes. This is along the lines indicated in the entry on Topological Quantum Field Theories from Compact Lie Groups:

    we imagine that we have an -topos H into which manifolds faithfully embed ManifoldsH. Then for every object XH there ought to be an (,n)-functor

    Bordn(*)Famn(*)

    given by sending a manifold Σ with boundaries ΣinΣΣout to the span of -groupoids

    H(Σin,X)H(Σ,X)H(Σout,X).

    If H is cohesive and X is of the form LConstA then we have H(Σ,X)Grpd(Π(Σ),A).

    Now, given a morphism XA (an “action functional”) there ought to be an n-stack object QCn which assigns an (,n)-category of quasicoherent sheaves of n-modules, and a canonical representation AQCn. Then the composite XAQCn ought to be the full action functional. And using this morphism there ought to be a lift of the above

    ZX:BordnFamn(*)

    to BordnFamn(nVect) or the like.

    And then quantization ought to be postcomposition with a canonical morphism

    :Famn(nVect)nVect.
  8. Hi Urs,

    ok, so the (,n) functor Bordn(*)Famn(*) associated with an object X is what I’m calling Bordn(X), while the n-stack object QCn is what I’ve implicitly been denoting nVect.

    So the way I figure things is that a morphism XQCn induces a morphism Bordn(X)Bordn(QCn); next Bordn(QCn) should have a natural lift ˜Bordn(QCn) to a functor taking values in Famn(nVect), and this should be the crucial point of the whole construction. Then the composition of these two maps should give

    Bordn(X)Famn(nVect)

    This is simply restating what you have just written above, stressing attention on Bordn(QCn). I mean: it doesn’t really matter how do we get to Bordn(QCn) (a way could be, e.g., via a cocycle BGBnU(1)QCn as we did several times); what really matters is wahat we are able to do once we are on Bordn(QCn), i.e., how do we canonically endow the oo-groupoids H(Σ,QCn) with morphisms to nVect.

    Push-forward along Σ*?

    • CommentRowNumber21.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeDec 20th 2010
    • (edited Dec 20th 2010)

    ok, so the (,n) functor Bordn(*)Famn(*) associated with an object X is what I’m calling Bordn(X),

    Okay, good.

    while the n-stack object QCn is what I’ve implicitly been denoting nVect.

    All right, this is less important, as this is just notation for an object that is kind of obvious. The QC-notation is a bit more suggestive for an object in a (,n)-sheaf topos, but maybe that need not be our primary concern at the moment.

    So the way I figure things is that a morphism XQCn induces a morphism Bordn(X)Bordn(QCn);

    Hm, okay, I see. That’s a slight variant of saying that the description in terms of that lift. Let me think about it.

    how do we canonically endow the oo-groupoids H(Σ,QCn) with morphisms to nVect.

    I think we should come back to that nice fact that τnd\mathbf{H}(\Pi(\Sigma_d),\mathbf{B}^n U(1)) \simeq \mathbf{B}^{n-d}U(1)$.

    This means that over Σd we get the data suitable for a transformation between the data over Σd1

    H(ΠΣd,BnU(1))H(ΠΣd1,BnU(1))H(ΠΣd1,BnU(1))Bn(d1)U(1)(n(d1)Vect).

    However, I am not yet sure how to organize this properly.

    • CommentRowNumber22.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeDec 21st 2010
    • (edited Dec 21st 2010)

    Domenico,

    please remind me: had you worked out the relative version of the truncation formula that is needed for what I said in the above comment?

    For Σ an d-dimensional monifold with boundary ΣinΣoutΣ, do we know how to get the natural transformation as above?

    • CommentRowNumber23.
    • CommentAuthordomenico_fiorenza
    • CommentTimeDec 21st 2010
    • (edited Dec 21st 2010)

    Hi Urs,

    yes and no: I had tried to think to that in terms of relative cohomology but was no able to get to a clean result.

    What confuses me about the truncation formula is that it seems to be much more restrictive than one would expect the theory to be: e.g., for n=1 one is delaing with line bundles, whereas things seem to go through for arbitrary vector bundles. That’s why I’d try to think directly in terms of H(,QCn) rather than in terms of H(,BnU(1)).

    The basic construction we need to understand, I think, is the following: given a flat vector bundle (or more in general a vector bundle equipped with a connection) on a space X, taking traces of holonomy gives a section of the End(1)-bundle over the loop space X, where 1 is the trivial -bundle. Here we are hiddenly using the fact that the trace gives a natural brane

    H(ΠS1,QC1)**Vect.

    where the bottom arrows pick out the algebra object in Vect.

    we have been around this several times, already, but I still think we have not got into the real mening of this; and indeed we are not able to see clearly which is the natural higher dimensional generalization. or at least I am not :)

  9. Hi Urs,

    I’m thinking to what you wrote in #19 again. That’s extremely neat, let me rewrite it in my words to see if I got the point: we have classical theories Bordn(*)Famn(nVect) and quantum theories Bord(*)nVect. The quantization of a classical theory is dealt with in FHLT, and is the natural functor

    :Famn(nVect)nvect

    The crucial question, then is: given any object X in a suitable (,1)-topos H, this gives an obvious funtor ZX:Bordn(*)Famn(*); can this functor be lifted to a classical theory? how?

    these lift I would call classical theories over X. Each of these gives, in particular a functor XnVect, corresponding to H)*,X)X. The probelm is how much does this functor tell us of the eventual classical theory over X?

    • CommentRowNumber25.
    • CommentAuthordomenico_fiorenza
    • CommentTimeDec 21st 2010
    • (edited Dec 21st 2010)

    Hey, wait, the answer is: fully dualizable object! Namely, Famn(nVect) is a symmetric monoidal (,n)-category, so by the cobordism hypotesis giving a classical field theory, i.e., a symmetric monoidal functor I:Bordn(*)Famn(nVect) is the same thing as giving a fully dualizable object in Famn(nVect), i.e. a suitable functor XnVect with X an oo-groupoid. More precisely, the datum of I is equivalent to the datum of I(*)={XnVect}

    Now, composing I with the forgetful morphism Famn(nVect)Famn(*) gives a functor F:Bordn(*)Famn(*) which (trivially) is lifted by I. If the functor F is representable, then it is represented by X, since F(*)=X. This would mean that I lifts a functor of the form H(,X) as in the posts above. On the other hand, making the fully dualizable object I(*) be the cornerstone of the construction makes the issue of the representability of F an interesting but probably not crucial question.

    So, coming back to the FHLT paper, I think we should ask ourselves the following questions:

    a) does Sumn:Famn(𝒞)𝒞 preserve full dualizable objects?

    b) are the “obvious” functors BGnVect induced by cocycles BGBnU(1) fully dualizable objects in Famn(nVect)?

    c) is the defining representation BnU(1)nVect a fully dualizable objects in Famn(nVect)?

    d) if X𝒞 is a fully dualizable object in Famn(𝒞) and YX is an n-functor, is the composition Y𝒞 a fully dualizable object in Famn(𝒞) (i.e., does c) implies b)? )

    • CommentRowNumber26.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeDec 21st 2010

    re #23, you write:

    What confuses me about the truncation formula is that it seems to be much more restrictive than one would expect the theory to be: e.g., for n=1 one is delaing with line bundles, whereas things seem to go through for arbitrary vector bundles.

    Yes, true, but I would be willing to believe that the case BnU(1) plays a special role that justifies it having its tailor-made theorems. After all, the Lagrangians for -Chern-Simons theory that we are trying to figure out the extended quantization of always take values in BnU(1)diff. So I wouldn’t be shocked if that case has a good general abstract quantization story, while a more general case does not.

    I think the truncation formula we have works too well to easily discard it. After all, it is a general abstract way of saying “the action is the integral over the Lagrangian”. That should not be light-heartedly be discrded! :-)

    • CommentRowNumber27.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeDec 21st 2010

    Concerning your other comments: ’ll think about it and come back to it a little later. Need to get something else done first.

  10. the truncation formula we have works too well to easily discard it. After all, it is a general abstract way of saying “the action is the integral over the Lagrangian”. That should not be light-heartedly be discrded! :-)

    a very good point! absolutely! :)

    concerning #25, the answer to a) is: trivially true. indeed that is an immediate consequence of the cobordism hypothesis and of the fact Sumn is a symmetric monoidal functor.

  11. concerning question b) in #25, the answer is yes at least for n=1 and n=2. Indeed, by the cobordism hypothesis, the value assigned to the point is a fully dualizable object, and in FHLT, what the functor I does on the point in the 1- and 2- dimensional case is said explicitely: it maps the point to the representation of BG induced by the cocycle c:BGBnU(1). I think one should expect the answer to be yes regardless of the dimension.