Not signed in (Sign In)

Not signed in

Want to take part in these discussions? Sign in if you have an account, or apply for one below

  • Sign in using OpenID

Site Tag Cloud

2-category 2-category-theory abelian-categories adjoint algebra algebraic algebraic-geometry algebraic-topology analysis analytic-geometry arithmetic arithmetic-geometry book bundles calculus categorical categories category category-theory chern-weil-theory cohesion cohesive-homotopy-type-theory cohomology colimits combinatorics complex complex-geometry computable-mathematics computer-science constructive cosmology deformation-theory descent diagrams differential differential-cohomology differential-equations differential-geometry digraphs duality elliptic-cohomology enriched fibration foundation foundations functional-analysis functor gauge-theory gebra geometric-quantization geometry graph graphs gravity grothendieck group group-theory harmonic-analysis higher higher-algebra higher-category-theory higher-differential-geometry higher-geometry higher-lie-theory higher-topos-theory homological homological-algebra homotopy homotopy-theory homotopy-type-theory index-theory integration integration-theory internal-categories k-theory lie-theory limits linear linear-algebra locale localization logic mathematics measure measure-theory modal modal-logic model model-category-theory monad monads monoidal monoidal-category-theory morphism motives motivic-cohomology nlab noncommutative noncommutative-geometry number-theory of operads operator operator-algebra order-theory pages pasting philosophy physics pro-object probability probability-theory quantization quantum quantum-field quantum-field-theory quantum-mechanics quantum-physics quantum-theory question representation representation-theory riemannian-geometry scheme schemes set set-theory sheaf simplicial space spin-geometry stable-homotopy-theory stack string string-theory superalgebra supergeometry svg symplectic-geometry synthetic-differential-geometry terminology theory topology topos topos-theory tqft type type-theory universal variational-calculus

Vanilla 1.1.10 is a product of Lussumo. More Information: Documentation, Community Support.

Welcome to nForum
If you want to take part in these discussions either sign in now (if you have an account), apply for one now (if you don't).
    • CommentRowNumber1.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeJan 3rd 2011
    • (edited Jan 3rd 2011)

    added to locale a section relation to toposes stating localic reflection

    • CommentRowNumber2.
    • CommentAuthorDavidRoberts
    • CommentTimeJan 3rd 2011

    locale, not ocale

    • CommentRowNumber3.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeJan 3rd 2011

    thanks, fixed.

    • CommentRowNumber4.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeJan 3rd 2011

    Added to locale remakrs on how the frame of subobjects Sub (*)τ 1Sub_{\mathcal{E}}(*) \simeq \tau_{\leq -1} is the subcategory of (1)(-1)-truncated objects and how this is the beginning of a pattern continued at n-localic (infinity,1)-topos.

    • CommentRowNumber5.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeMar 16th 2011

    Have added to locale in the section Category of locales two theorems from the Elephant on the externalization of internal locales (needed in the discussion of Bohrification)

    • CommentRowNumber6.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeJul 8th 2011

    At locale in the section relation to topological spaces I have tried to make some of the statements more pronounced.

    • CommentRowNumber7.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeJul 25th 2011

    I have made more explicit in the discussion of localic reflection at locale that Sh:LocaleToposSh : Locale \to Topos is fully faithful in fact as a 2-functor.

    The discussion of this point in the entry would deserve a bit of expansion. Maybe I find time to expand on it later.

    • CommentRowNumber8.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeJul 25th 2011

    I realized that we never stated the definition of the 2-category (or (1,2)-category) of locales. So I have now added it to the Definition-section at Locale.

    • CommentRowNumber9.
    • CommentAuthorTobyBartels
    • CommentTimeJul 25th 2011

    You mean at locale; Locale already had it!

    • CommentRowNumber10.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeJul 25th 2011
    • (edited Jul 25th 2011)

    Oh. dear, I should take a break :-) I did look for it, but didn’t see it! Thanks.

    Anyway, I have now added to Locale, too, the precise definition, and some more pointers.

    • CommentRowNumber11.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeDec 6th 2011

    Added to locale the observation that frames are the same as lex total posets, by way of introducing connections between locales and toposes.

    • CommentRowNumber12.
    • CommentAuthorMike Shulman
    • CommentTimeDec 6th 2011

    Nice, thanks! Should we have a page lex-total category with Street’s theorem on it?

    • CommentRowNumber13.
    • CommentAuthorCharles Rezk
    • CommentTimeMay 20th 2019

    The second paragraph of Locale says:

    For example, there is a locale of all surjections from natural numbers (thought of as forming the discrete space NN) to real numbers (forming the real line RR): the locale of real numbers. This local has no points, since there are no such surjections, but it contains many nontrivial open subspaces; these open subspaces are generated by a family parametrised by n:Nn\colon N and x:Rx\colon R; the basic open associated to nn and xx may be described as {f:NR|f(n)=x}\{f\colon N \twoheadrightarrow R \;|\; f(n) = x\}.

    Can someone explain exactly what this means, or at least give a reference?

    • CommentRowNumber14.
    • CommentAuthorDavid_Corfield
    • CommentTimeMay 20th 2019

    Capitalised ’Locale’ is redirected to Loc, the category. So you mean the lower case version locale.

    Does the description at locale of real numbers help? It seems to be largely the work of Toby.

    • CommentRowNumber15.
    • CommentAuthorCharles Rezk
    • CommentTimeMay 20th 2019

    Yes I mean locale. The locale of real numbers doesn’t help at all. In any case I would guess that the particular sets (locales?) NN and RR are basically irrelevant for this example. (Except for having |N|<|R||N|\lt|R|, which is supposed to imply there are no points.) I just want to know what definition is underlying this example.

    • CommentRowNumber16.
    • CommentAuthorCharles Rezk
    • CommentTimeMay 20th 2019
    • (edited May 20th 2019)

    Here’s my speculation, though it doesn’t seem to work right. Let XX and YY be sets, and let 𝒫\mathcal{P} be the poset of “finite partial graphs” in X×YX\times Y, i.e., finite subsets ΓX×Y\Gamma\subseteq X\times Y such that the composite ΓX×YX\Gamma\to X\times Y \to X is injective. Let 𝒪\mathcal{O} be the collection of upward-closed subsets of 𝒫\mathcal{P}: this set is supposed to be the collection of “opens” in the locale.

    Given any function f:XYf\colon X\to Y let U f𝒪U_f\in \mathcal{O} be the set of all Γ𝒫\Gamma\in \mathcal{P} such that ΓΓ f\Gamma\cup \Gamma_f is not the graph of any function: it’s the set of finite partial graphs inconsistent with ff. Note that U f𝒫U_f\neq \mathcal{P} since U f\varnothing\notin U_f, and I can show that U fU_f is non-trivially an intersection of non-maximal elements of 𝒪\mathcal{O} if and only if ff is not surjective. That is, surjective functions give rise to points in the locale 𝒪\mathcal{O}. What I can’t prove is that these are the only points in the locale.

    Edit. Nevermind that doesn’t make sense anyway. But I expect they mean some kind of example along these lines.

    • CommentRowNumber17.
    • CommentAuthorMike Shulman
    • CommentTimeMay 20th 2019

    The locale of surjections XYX\to Y is the classifying locale of the propositional geometric theory of surjections XYX\to Y. There are basic propositions “f(x)=yf(x)=y” (an atomic formula) for each xXx\in X and yYy\in Y, and then axioms like xX yYf(x)=y\vdash_{x\in X} \bigvee_{y\in Y} f(x)=y and (f(x)=y)(f(x)=y) xX,yyY(f(x)=y) \wedge (f(x)=y') \vdash_{x\in X,y\neq y'\in Y} \bot to make it a function and yY xXf(x)=y\vdash_{y\in Y} \bigvee_{x\in X} f(x)=y to make it surjective. So the opens of the locale are generated by these propositions “f(x)=yf(x)=y” under finite meet and arbitrary join, modulo those axioms. This can be re-expressed in terms of partial functions in a way kind of like you say, but I don’t remember (and don’t have time to work out) exactly how it goes. But with this description, the points of the locale are, by the universal property of classifying locales (or equivalently, by the universal property of a frame presented by generators and relations), precisely surjections XYX\to Y.

    • CommentRowNumber18.
    • CommentAuthorCharles Rezk
    • CommentTimeMay 23rd 2019

    Thanks Mike. I would still love a reference for this. It looks to me that what I was describing above is the locale of “partial graphs in X×YX\times Y”; at least, the points are precisely the partial graphs. I assume the additional axioms are imposed by choosing appropriate sublocales.

    • CommentRowNumber19.
    • CommentAuthorMike Shulman
    • CommentTimeMay 24th 2019

    It’s C1.2.8 in Sketches of an Elephant.

    • CommentRowNumber20.
    • CommentAuthorCharles Rezk
    • CommentTimeJun 7th 2019

    Thanks Mike.

    Here’s a brief sketch of the construction (where I’ve unwound most of the terminology Johnstone uses here).

    Fix discrete spaces XX and YY, and let M= XYM=\prod_X Y with the usual product topology. For a finite subset SYS\subseteq Y write M S={fM|Sf(X)}M_S=\{f\in M\;|\; S\subseteq f(X)\}, the subset of functions which map onto SS. Let 𝒪\mathcal{O} be the collection of open subsets UMU\subseteq M such that

    for all open VMV\subseteq M and finite SYS\subseteq Y, we have that VM SUV\cap M_S\subseteq U implies VUV\subseteq U.

    The claims are that:

    1. 𝒪\mathcal{O} is a complete lattice satisfying the infinite distributive law, i.e., it corresponds to a locale.

    2. If XX is infinite then 𝒪\varnothing\in \mathcal{O} and M𝒪M\in \mathcal{O}, e.g., 𝒪\mathcal{O} is a non-trivial locale when XX is infinite and YY is non-empty.

    3. The points of 𝒪\mathcal{O} correspond exactly to surjective functions XYX\to Y.

    In particular, if |X|<|Y|\infty\leq |X| \lt |Y| then 𝒪\mathcal{O} is a non-trivial pointless locale. (Johnstone in the example assumes X=X=\mathbb{N}, but as far as I can tell the construction is entirely general.)

    It is easy to see that 𝒪\mathcal{O} is closed under pairwise intersections of open sets and contains MM, so has pairwise meets and a top element. To show it is a locale, you need to know that for every open set UU there is a smallest open set j(U)j(U) which contains UU and is an element of 𝒪\mathcal{O}. The recipe for jj is to define for any open set UU,

    h(U):= VM SUV, h(U) := \bigcup_{V\cap M_S\subseteq U} V,

    where the union ranges over all open VUV\subseteq U and finite SYS\subseteq Y satisfying the condition. Then iterate hh some possibly transfinite number of times to get j(U)j(U). Then j()j(\varnothing) is the bottom element and U i=j(U i)\bigvee U_i = j(\bigcup U_i). The key observation is that hh preserves pairwise intersection and has exactly elements of 𝒪\mathcal{O} as its fixed points, whence jj has these same properties.

    More conceptually: 𝒪\mathcal{O} is the limit in Locale of the family of subspaces M SM_S of MM indexed by the poset of all finite SYS\subseteq Y; compare with the limit in Top, which is just the subspace SM S\bigcap_S M_S of surjective functions. (Johnntone says “intersection of sublocales” here, but I think it is also an example of a limit in Locale this context, as is the intersection subspace in Top.)

    Unrelated remark: Apparently the TeX engine on this thing displays the same character for \varnothing\backslash varnothing (\varnothing) and \emptyset\backslash emptyset (\emptyset), which is unfortunate since \emptyset is so ugly.

    • CommentRowNumber21.
    • CommentAuthorMike Shulman
    • CommentTimeJun 8th 2019

    Thanks for writing that out! It would be useful to add it to some nlab page, maybe locale?

    I generally prefer \emptyset to \varnothing; I find the latter uglier than the former. But if you really want the latter you may be able to get it with unicode &#8709; (∅).

    • CommentRowNumber22.
    • CommentAuthorTobyBartels
    • CommentTimeSep 25th 2019

    Web page for Picado & Pultr 2012.

    diff, v76, current

    • CommentRowNumber23.
    • CommentAuthorTobyBartels
    • CommentTimeSep 25th 2019

    I added a bit about the locale of surjections discussed in comments #13–#21, only at the level of detail of Mike #17 (actually less detail than that), not Charles #20.

    • CommentRowNumber24.
    • CommentAuthorTobyBartels
    • CommentTimeFeb 2nd 2020

    The direct-image functor preserves joins, not meets.

    diff, v78, current

    • CommentRowNumber25.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeFeb 2nd 2020
    • (edited Feb 2nd 2020)

    Toby: no. This is not “direct image”, since direct image maps do not (generally) take opens to opens. Rather, we are taking an adjoint O(X)O(Y)O(X) \to O(Y) to a frame map O(Y)O(X)O(Y) \to O(X), and since frame maps are left exact left adjoints, we want here its right adjoint, playing a role analogous to geometric morphisms between toposes.

    • CommentRowNumber26.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeFeb 3rd 2020

    (Rolled back to previous version.)

    • CommentRowNumber27.
    • CommentAuthorTobyBartels
    • CommentTimeFeb 7th 2020

    Sorry, I thought that it was a typo (well, something analogous to that, involving thinking about things backwards), but it was me who was thinking backwards! (left vs right adjoint).

    • CommentRowNumber28.
    • CommentAuthorTobyBartels
    • CommentTimeFeb 7th 2020
    • (edited Feb 7th 2020)

    Although a rollback is a dangerous tool, since I also made some other (more minor) edits. I just used that tool myself to restore my other edits; but if all that you did was to roll back my edit and add your remark (edit: and change ‘This category’ to ‘The category LocaleLocale’), then everything is OK now.

    • CommentRowNumber29.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeFeb 8th 2020

    Sorry if I missed those other edits. Looks good now.

    • CommentRowNumber30.
    • CommentAuthorDmitri Pavlov
    • CommentTimeMar 22nd 2020

    Added another description of localic direct images for topological spaces.

    diff, v82, current

  1. Added reference for the construction of the locale of surjections N -> R.

    Alfredo Álvarez

    diff, v83, current

    • CommentRowNumber32.
    • CommentAuthorDmitri Pavlov
    • CommentTimeFeb 24th 2021

    Redirects: map of locales, morphism of locales, etc.

    diff, v84, current

    • CommentRowNumber33.
    • CommentAuthorDmitri Pavlov
    • CommentTimeJul 3rd 2021

    Added the following text:


    Examples

    General topology

    As explained above, the functor from topological spaces to locales provides a very large collection of examples. When restricted to sober topological spaces, this functor becomes fully faihtful and its essential images consists of spatial locales.

    If excluded middle fails, many classical examples, such as the locale of real numbers, can cease to be spatial.

    Naturally, one is interested in examples of locales that are not spatial, and a few are given below.

    Measure theory

    An amazing feature of pointfree topology is that it contains not only point-set general topology, but also point-set measure theory, again as a full subcategory.

    Specifically, recall from the duality between geometry and algebra that various categories of commutative algebras are contravariantly equivalent to certain corresponding categories of spaces. The category of algebras relevant for measure theory is the category of commutative von Neumann algebras and ultraweak *-homomorphisms; it is widely accepted that dropping the commutativity condition and passing to the opposite category yields the correct category of noncommutative measurable spaces.

    The category of commutative von Neumann algebras is contravariantly equivalent to several other categories:

    The last category is particularly interesting: it is a full subcategory of locales, which means that measure theory embeds into pointfree topology, which means that methods and results from pointfree topology can be used right away in measure theory. This stands in contrast to the traditional point-set treatments, where two rather different formalisms must be developed for point-set topological spaces and for point-set measurable spaces.

    With the exception of discrete locales, measurable locales are never spatial.

    Intersections of dense sublocales

    Another important source of nonspatial sublocales is given by intersections (of arbitrary cardinality) of dense sublocales.

    Again, in contrast to the point-set setting, where the Baire category theorem identifies the rather restrictive conditions under which the intersection of dense topological subspaces is again dense, in the pointfree setting arbitrary intersections of dense sublocales are always dense.

    In particular, one can intersection all dense sublocales of a given locale, which always produces a nonspatial locale, unless the original locale is discrete. This is the double negation sublocale.

    But there are other interesting examples. Connecting to measure theory, we can consider a valuation ν\nu on a given locale LL and take the intersection of all sublocales SS such that ν(S)=ν(1)\nu(S)=\nu(1). The resulting sublocale can be seen as the smallest sublocale with a measure 0 complement.


    diff, v85, current

    • CommentRowNumber34.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeJul 3rd 2021

    Thanks!! That’s excellent.

    (We should really have an entry noncommutative measure theory…)

    diff, v86, current

    • CommentRowNumber35.
    • CommentAuthormaxsnew
    • CommentTimeSep 9th 2022

    Does Johnstone’s example here have anything to do with Andrej Bauer’s recent work on a topos where the reals are countable? I.e., should the fact that the classifying space for a surjection from N to R is non-trivial already be a proof that there is a non-trivial topos where the reals are countable? Though this is a geometric theory and Andrej’s is an elementary topos so I’m not sure what the relationship is.

    More generally a geometric theory having a classifying locale with no points just means there’s no propositional models in Set, but it suggests that there are alternative toposes where it would have points. This seems to be a nice thing to mention (if I didn’t botch it).

    • CommentRowNumber36.
    • CommentAuthorMike Shulman
    • CommentTimeSep 10th 2022

    should the fact that the classifying space for a surjection from N to R is non-trivial already be a proof that there is a non-trivial topos where the reals are countable?

    I don’t think so. The “real numbers” in the base topos (e.g. Set) become countable in the topos of sheaves on that classifying locale, but they won’t be the same as the internally defined real numbers in that topos.

    More generally a geometric theory having a classifying locale with no points just means there’s no propositional models in Set, but it suggests that there are alternative toposes where it would have points.

    Yes, that’s right. (Although terminology-wise, being “propositional” is a property of a theory, not of its models.) In particular, the classifying topos of that theory itself contains a generic model of the theory, corresponding to the identity geometric morphism.

  2. Added reference

    Anonymous

    diff, v93, current

    • CommentRowNumber38.
    • CommentAuthorGuest
    • CommentTimeMay 28th 2023
    In the 1984 paper "An Extension of the Galois Theory of Grothendieck" by André Joyal and Myles Tierney what you call a frame they called a locale, and the opposite category they called the category of Spaces, which makes more sense than the nomenclature used on this page and elsewhere. Was the Joyal/Tierney paper missed? Why this new bad choice of names? I think the choice of a name can make connections better, e.g. the Joyal/Tierney concept of a space is a natural generalization of the concept of a topological space. What am I missing here?
    ---- Perplexed
    • CommentRowNumber39.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeMay 28th 2023

    That it’s a “bad choice” is your opinion. I’m not convinced “space” makes “more sense” than “locale”; one could argue that “space” is a poor choice because it is apt to be confused with an ordinary topological space.

    In any case, the real point is that what “we” at the nLab call a frame is what everyone else besides Joyal and Tierney calls a frame, and what we call a locale is what everyone but J and T calls a locale. So we’re just sticking with the established convention and terminology – for better or worse. This makes it easier and generally less confusing for others to compare what we do with what other people do, save for some outliers (like J and T in this case).

    (Full disclosure: as I was a Tierney student, I often slip and write “locale” when I mean “frame”, and then I’ll catch myself later.)

    • CommentRowNumber40.
    • CommentAuthorGuest
    • CommentTimeMay 28th 2023
    I guess it's like the flow of electricity being in the direction of 'positive' charges when in reality it's the 'negative' charges that are moving. We're stuck with it.
    I'm happy to hear that you were a student of Tierney. The paper I referred to is brilliant and at one time in my life I tried to justify it's position in an arbitrary topos via it's internal language and logic.
    ---- not so much perplexed
    • CommentRowNumber41.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeMay 28th 2023

    It is brilliant (and influential), but in some places it’s a bit terse and demands a persistent effort. Some time ago I saw here mention of an expository paper that goes through the Joyal-Tierney monograph more gently. There may be some nLab articles on this in the foreseeable future.

    • CommentRowNumber42.
    • CommentAuthorGuest
    • CommentTimeMay 29th 2023

    The word “space” is overloaded in mathematics. Alongside topological spaces and locales, there are also formal spaces. There is no reason why locales should take precedent over the others.

    • CommentRowNumber43.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeJun 1st 2023

    Added to the bibliography a 1972 paper of Isbell, who introduced the term “locale”.

    diff, v94, current

    • CommentRowNumber44.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeOct 24th 2023
    • (edited Oct 24th 2023)

    added pointer to the recent

    establishing a model category of locales which makes the reflection of sober topological spaces a Quillen adjunction to the sober-restriction of the classical model structure on topological spaces.

    diff, v96, current