Want to take part in these discussions? Sign in if you have an account, or apply for one below
Vanilla 1.1.10 is a product of Lussumo. More Information: Documentation, Community Support.
I’ve inserted some proofs of statements made at Heyting algebra, particular on the “regular element” left adjoint to the full inclusion .
The proof that preserves implication seemed harder than I was expecting it to be. Or maybe my proof is a clumsy one? If anyone knows a shorter route to this result, I’d be interested.
That’s intriguing! I would have expected there to be an abstract reason for that, but I can’t think of one right now. Abstract nonsense implies that has a left adjoint, whose unit is then necessarily a Heyting algebra map, but then how can we identify the Boolean reflection with ?
Actually, your comment made me realize how all this is connected with the double negation translation (a page I have just started), which I would imagine requires machinations of the sort worked out at Heyting algebra.
Here’s something that actually took me by surprise: double negation on a Heyting algebra preserves not only finite meets, but the implication operation as well! It follows from this that the inclusion also preserves implication (contrary to what was stated before at Heyting algebra, so I guess this will take someone else besides me by surprise (-: ).
That does at first seem a little surprising; but then when I think about it in terms of logic, it’s obvious. (-:
Sorry, could you explain what you mean? Is there an easier way to see this than what I put down in Heyting algebra: Proofs?
Todd, I just broke your last link by making it permanent: Heyting algebra: Proofs.
No, I think I was jumping to unjustified conclusions and being confused, sorry.
Toby, I see you made edits at Heyting algebra, in particular putting the remark in an environment. But it renders funny, and I can’t see what’s wrong with the syntax. Does it look funny to you, and if so can you fix it?
It’s an subtle typo; I had
+-- {: un_remark}
when it should be
+-- {: .un_remark}
It’s fixed now.
Oops! Yes, I see it now – thanks.
when it should be
+-- {: .un_remark}
I have a general suggestion: let’s use
+-- {: .num_remark}
and similar by default. That’s more useful when an entry grows. (And all entries will grow eventually…)
I think that’s a good suggestion, Urs (and I’ve begun doing that, but not consistently).
I’d like to propose another suggestion: when including redirects, make a point of including plural forms. That way a link can be made directly from the plural, without extra fuss.
If we do use numbered theorem environements, I think we should always also include an anchor name:
+-- {: .num_remark #MyRemark}
IIRC there is an instiki bug that rears its head when some, but not all, of the numbered theorems on a given page have anchor names assigned.
Yes, very true.
On the other hand, maybe there is hope that this bug will disappear some day? I keep liking the idea that the software helps me save time, instead of me having to invest time to work around it…
Bug or no bug, there’s not much point to numbering the theorems/remarks/etc if you can’t refer to them later by number. And the only safe way to do that is with the anchors.
Bug or no bug, there’s not much point to numbering the theorems/remarks/etc if you can’t refer to them later by number. And the only safe way to do that is with the anchors.
That’s what we currently do anyway, being forced by the bug: if I want to refer to something by number, I need to anchor everything in between in order for the numbers to come out right.
But what I am hesitant (no: unwilling) to do is to preemptively think up anchor names for everything in sight even before I refer to a single one. It would be good, I agree, but there is some limit being reached here.
But what I am hesitant (no: unwilling) to do is to preemptively think up anchor names for everything in sight even before I refer to a single one.
Me too. But in that case, I just leave them unnumbered until I decide that I wish to refer to them.
I agree, the bug should be fixed; and when it is, then you can just make everything numbered to start with, without thinking of names. However, so long as you cannot think of a name, then numbering it gives you no additional benefit (and leaving it unnumbered works around the bug, while we have it).
I’ve moved the comments on theorem numbering to their own thread: Theorem numbering.
I don’t know if what follows is shorter, but I think is clearer:
First, factor the monad as
and call the reflection also ; the inclusion will be implicit. We obviously have
From 3 we have that for
Now, everything is easy once we note that
is an exponential ideal in
This is almost immediate from the definition of ; for arbitrary :
that is,
Now, from this if , then
so that and we get exponential ideal.
We have, for :
Note that for trivially
and from this both
are closed. We get then closed.
The only thing left is
Every functor between cartesian categories is colax monoidal, which here amounts to
(this is the easy one, of course). For the reverse, first note that Kleisli extension yields
Now, for
Applying the same steps to , we get a bijection
Taking the map given by the unit at ,
we get what we were looking for:
This is just Proposition A.4.3.1 of the Elephant adapted to this context.
As for being a Boolean algebra, it follows at once from double negation in being just the double negation of resctricted to . Then, for :
Summing up,
the inclusion is
the reflection is
From this we get that
double negation is
By symmetry of , we get
and . It’d be nice if being De Morgan would be equivalent to this adjunction being an ambijunction
one such Heyting algebra is automatically De Morgan; guess there should be examples of De Morgan Heyting algebras for which is not left adjoint to .
Sorry, eparejatobes (I don’t know your given name) – how is the second equation in the second line after
is an exponeital ideal in
(where there is a typo – you mean instead of ) supposed to be obvious? I mean, I can prove it, but it’s not totally obvious to me without some calculation.
Hi Todd,
it’s Eduardo :)
Sorry, eparejatobes (I don’t know your given name) – how is the second equation in the second line after
L¬¬ is an exponeital ideal in L (where there is a typo – you mean y instead of a) supposed to be obvious? I mean, I can prove it, but it’s not totally obvious to me without some calculation.
Whoah! that’s wrong in many ways! don’t know what I was thinking when I wrote that. I mean, it may be true, but not obvious at all, and in fact I don’t know how to prove it :) Thanks for spotting it. I’ve been looking for a way to fix this, and found a nice proof of perserving finite products in this lecture notes:
So, here follows what I have:
First of all, let’s state some properties of negation which will be of great use later on; most of them are direct consequences of the definition ; note that this means that
We can factor the monad coming from the adjunction as:
Let’s see first that the reflection preserves meets; as a reflective subcategory, we have that finite meets in are just finite meets in ; so that presrving finite meets is equivalent to
One inclusion is always true for a functor between posets with finite meets
(every functor between cartesian cats is colax monoidal). Now, for the other one:
is equivalent by adjunction to
reorganizing this to
we can apply 3 to get
doing the same with we arrive at
which is always the case, via adjunction and the unit of :
From this we get that double negation also preserves finite meets.
This is in the Elephant, A.4.3.1. The key is noting that
because of idempotent. Now, taking , we have
So we have
So taking we get
that is, is an exponential ideal. From this, it is immediate that
From this is easy to get that is a Boolean algebra etc.
What I don’t know how to get is that also the reflection is closed. I mean, in a different way than what you have. Really nice the expression:
haven’t seen that before.
So, sorry for the noise :)
Apart from that, does anyone knows something about Heyting algebras for which ? thanks!
1 to 22 of 22