Not signed in (Sign In)

Not signed in

Want to take part in these discussions? Sign in if you have an account, or apply for one below

  • Sign in using OpenID

Site Tag Cloud

2-category 2-category-theory abelian-categories adjoint algebra algebraic algebraic-geometry algebraic-topology analysis analytic-geometry arithmetic arithmetic-geometry book bundles calculus categorical categories category category-theory chern-weil-theory cohesion cohesive-homotopy-type-theory cohomology colimits combinatorics complex complex-geometry computable-mathematics computer-science constructive cosmology deformation-theory descent diagrams differential differential-cohomology differential-equations differential-geometry digraphs duality elliptic-cohomology enriched fibration foundation foundations functional-analysis functor gauge-theory gebra geometric-quantization geometry graph graphs gravity grothendieck group group-theory harmonic-analysis higher higher-algebra higher-category-theory higher-differential-geometry higher-geometry higher-lie-theory higher-topos-theory homological homological-algebra homotopy homotopy-theory homotopy-type-theory index-theory integration integration-theory internal-categories k-theory lie-theory limits linear linear-algebra locale localization logic mathematics measure measure-theory modal modal-logic model model-category-theory monad monads monoidal monoidal-category-theory morphism motives motivic-cohomology nlab noncommutative noncommutative-geometry number-theory of operads operator operator-algebra order-theory pages pasting philosophy physics pro-object probability probability-theory quantization quantum quantum-field quantum-field-theory quantum-mechanics quantum-physics quantum-theory question representation representation-theory riemannian-geometry scheme schemes set set-theory sheaf simplicial space spin-geometry stable-homotopy-theory stack string string-theory superalgebra supergeometry svg symplectic-geometry synthetic-differential-geometry terminology theory topology topos topos-theory tqft type type-theory universal variational-calculus

Vanilla 1.1.10 is a product of Lussumo. More Information: Documentation, Community Support.

Welcome to nForum
If you want to take part in these discussions either sign in now (if you have an account), apply for one now (if you don't).
    • CommentRowNumber1.
    • CommentAuthorTobyBartels
    • CommentTimeJun 8th 2012

    To anybody who can think constructively (Mike at least):

    Given a real number aa, and let XX be the Kuratowski-finite set {y,z}\{y, z\} such that y=zy = z iff a0a \ne 0 (in the strong sense of apartness). Consider the ring of polynomials with real coefficients and variables from the set XX. Are the polynomials aya y and aza z equal?

    (The polynomial functions from X\mathbb{R}^X to \mathbb{R} defined by them are certainly equal, but I’m asking about polynomials as formal expressions. For example, the polynomials xx and x 2x^2 are not equal, even in the ring of one-variable polynomials with coefficients from 𝔽 2\mathbb{F}_2.)

    • CommentRowNumber2.
    • CommentAuthorMike Shulman
    • CommentTimeJun 8th 2012

    I must be missing something; why are the polynomial functions they define equal?

    • CommentRowNumber3.
    • CommentAuthorIngoBlechschmidt
    • CommentTimeJun 9th 2012
    • (edited Jun 9th 2012)

    I believe the following argument shows that the polynomial functions are equal:

    Let φ X\varphi \in \mathbb{R}^{X}, we want to show aφ(y)=aφ(z)a \varphi(y) = a \varphi(z). For any n1n \geq 1, we have a0a \neq 0 or |a|1n\left|a\right| \le \frac{1}{n}. In both cases the inequality |aφ(y)aφ(z)|1n|φ(y)φ(z)|\left|a \varphi(y) - a \varphi(z)\right| \leq \frac{1}{n} \cdot \left|\varphi(y) - \varphi(z)\right| follows. As |φ(y)φ(z)|\left|\varphi(y) - \varphi(z)\right| is fixed, this shows that indeed |aφ(y)aφ(z)|=0\left|a \varphi(y) - a \varphi(z)\right| = 0.

    I don’t have an answer to the original question.

    • CommentRowNumber4.
    • CommentAuthorMike Shulman
    • CommentTimeJun 9th 2012

    Nice argument! I’m afraid I don’t have an answer to the original question either, though. I don’t see any reason why they should be equal, but I don’t immediately see how to build a counterexample either.

    • CommentRowNumber5.
    • CommentAuthorjcmckeown
    • CommentTimeJun 10th 2012

    I shouldn't be distracting myself with this, but what does "=" mean, here? Or is that part of the question, too?

    • CommentRowNumber6.
    • CommentAuthorMike Shulman
    • CommentTimeJun 10th 2012

    Well, the real numbers are a set, as are Toby’s set XX and the polynomial ring, so == means equality in those sets. Are you asking about how those sets are defined? The set XX, for instance, is defined as the quotient of the two-element set {y,z}\{y,z\} by the equivalence relation which sets yzy\sim z iff a0a\neq 0 (and of course yyy\sim y and zzz\sim z unconditionally).

    • CommentRowNumber7.
    • CommentAuthorTobyBartels
    • CommentTimeJun 10th 2012

    JC is right to ask; the question is what equality in [X]\mathbb{R}[X] should be. Of course, [X]\mathbb{R}[X] is the free commutative \mathbb{R}-algebra on the set XX, but what’s an \mathbb{R}-algebra? If this is simply a set equipped with some operations and commutative diagrams (including one unary scalar multiplication operation for each real number), then ay=aza y = a z in [X]\mathbb{R}[X] iff a=0a = 0 or a0a \ne 0 (so if ay=aza y = a z for every aa, then the lesser limited principle of omniscience holds). However, if an \mathbb{R}-algebra is equipped with a tight apartness that all operations respect and a binary scalar multiplication operation ×BB\mathbb{R} \times B \to B that also respects it and the usual apartness on \mathbb{R} (in the sense of being strongly extensional), then ay=aza y = a z necessarily. So that answers my question, I guess.

    • CommentRowNumber8.
    • CommentAuthorMike Shulman
    • CommentTimeJun 11th 2012

    Hmm, I was about to say that I thought Ingo’s argument would work for polynomials too. Namely, define the norm of a polynomial to be the supremum of the absolute values of its coefficients. Then since either |a|<1n{|a|}\lt \frac{1}{n} or a0a\neq 0, in both cases ayaz<2n{\Vert a y - a z \Vert }\lt \frac{2}{n}, and this holds for all nn, so ayaz=0{\Vert a y - a z \Vert} = 0 and thus ay=aza y = a z. What definition of [X]\mathbb{R}[X] is that using?

    • CommentRowNumber9.
    • CommentAuthorTobyBartels
    • CommentTimeJun 11th 2012
    • (edited Jun 11th 2012)

    How do you know that this supremum exists? (It always exists as a lower real number, but the comparison law is invalid for those, so we must prove that the supremum is located.) In particular, the norm of ayaza y - a z is 00 if y=zy = z, but this norm is aa if yzy \ne z.

    With the second definition of [X]\mathbb{R}[X] (with apartness), I we can prove that ayaza y - a z must have a located norm (although we can’t prove this for an arbitrary polynomial in [X]\mathbb{R}[X]), so the argument will still go through; but not with the first definition.

    • CommentRowNumber10.
    • CommentAuthorMike Shulman
    • CommentTimeJun 11th 2012

    Ah, right. (You can probably tell that I don’t work with constructive real numbers much.)