Processing math: 100%
Not signed in (Sign In)

Not signed in

Want to take part in these discussions? Sign in if you have an account, or apply for one below

  • Sign in using OpenID

Site Tag Cloud

2-category 2-category-theory abelian-categories adjoint algebra algebraic algebraic-geometry algebraic-topology analysis analytic-geometry arithmetic arithmetic-geometry book bundles calculus categorical categories category category-theory chern-weil-theory cohesion cohesive-homotopy-type-theory cohomology colimits combinatorics complex complex-geometry computable-mathematics computer-science constructive cosmology definitions deformation-theory descent diagrams differential differential-cohomology differential-equations differential-geometry digraphs duality elliptic-cohomology enriched fibration finite foundation foundations functional-analysis functor gauge-theory gebra geometric-quantization geometry graph graphs gravity grothendieck group group-theory harmonic-analysis higher higher-algebra higher-category-theory higher-differential-geometry higher-geometry higher-lie-theory higher-topos-theory homological homological-algebra homotopy homotopy-theory homotopy-type-theory index-theory integration integration-theory k-theory lie-theory limits linear linear-algebra locale localization logic mathematics measure-theory modal modal-logic model model-category-theory monad monads monoidal monoidal-category-theory morphism motives motivic-cohomology nlab noncommutative noncommutative-geometry number-theory of operads operator operator-algebra order-theory pages pasting philosophy physics pro-object probability probability-theory quantization quantum quantum-field quantum-field-theory quantum-mechanics quantum-physics quantum-theory question representation representation-theory riemannian-geometry scheme schemes set set-theory sheaf simplicial space spin-geometry stable-homotopy-theory stack string string-theory superalgebra supergeometry svg symplectic-geometry synthetic-differential-geometry terminology theory topology topos topos-theory tqft type type-theory universal variational-calculus

Vanilla 1.1.10 is a product of Lussumo. More Information: Documentation, Community Support.

Welcome to nForum
If you want to take part in these discussions either sign in now (if you have an account), apply for one now (if you don't).
    • CommentRowNumber1.
    • CommentAuthorMike Shulman
    • CommentTimeAug 28th 2012

    Started work on syntopogenous space.

    • CommentRowNumber2.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeAug 28th 2012

    Working on… what? :-)

    • CommentRowNumber3.
    • CommentAuthorMike Shulman
    • CommentTimeAug 28th 2012

    Is that a question addressed to me?

    • CommentRowNumber4.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeAug 28th 2012

    I was just joking… the term “syntopogenous” is one I’d never heard of, and it just sounds so esoteric. Have you known about them a long time?

    • CommentRowNumber5.
    • CommentAuthorMike Shulman
    • CommentTimeAug 28th 2012

    No, I just read about them recently. As far as I know, they aren’t good for anything; I’m just amused that they exist.

    • CommentRowNumber6.
    • CommentAuthorMike Shulman
    • CommentTimeAug 28th 2012

    And that the “underlying topology” functor UnifTop (and others) can be described as a coreflection.

    • CommentRowNumber7.
    • CommentAuthorMike Shulman
    • CommentTimeAug 28th 2012

    I think I’m done with syntopogenous space now, by the way.

    • CommentRowNumber8.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeJun 27th 2014

    Should there be a clause in condition 2 of topogenous relation that ABδC iff AδC or BδC? (What’s there involves unions only in the second variable.) It seems you’d need this to justify the claim that the opposite of a topogenous relation is also topogenous.

    Is it correct that inserting this clause doesn’t affect any of the results on this page?

    • CommentRowNumber9.
    • CommentAuthorTobyBartels
    • CommentTimeJun 27th 2014

    Yes, definitely. I'll fix it.

    Is it correct that inserting this clause doesn’t affect any of the results on this page?

    On the contrary, inserting this clause is necessary to make many of them true!

    • CommentRowNumber10.
    • CommentAuthorTobyBartels
    • CommentTimeJul 18th 2014

    Some changes made, mainly to mention (and ) earlier and to clarify the role of nontriviality/reflexivity.

    • CommentRowNumber11.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeDec 28th 2014
    • (edited Dec 28th 2014)

    Behind the scenes there has been some further discussion with Victor Porton, including this discussion at MO with an illuminating response from Mamuka Jibladze. This has produced what I regard as (potentially) the most useful way of regarding topogenous relations on a set X: they can be identified with closed subsets CβX×βX containing the diagonal, that is to say with reflexive relations from βX to itself in the pretopos of compact Hausdorff spaces. I have added this remark to syntopogenous space.

    (Briefly: a map PX×PX2 which preserves finite joins in separate arguments amounts to a join-preserving map PXPX2 where the tensor product is just that of join-semilattices viewed as (idempotent) commutative monoids. This tensor product gives the coproduct of commutative rigs, and this coproduct is one of Boolean algebras as well. By Stone duality, this corresponds to the product βX×βX, where the poset of join-preserving maps as above is dual to the poset of ideals in CompHaus(βX×βX,2), i.e., is dual to the topology of the Zariski spectrum βX×βX. This leads to the identification with closed subsets CβX×βX. Details can be found at my article topogeny.)

    I have not tried to work out what a syntopogeny is from this point of view. But it seems like potentially useful point of view, since so much is known about β.

    • CommentRowNumber12.
    • CommentAuthorMike Shulman
    • CommentTimeDec 29th 2014

    Interesting! How does the correspondence act concretely? E.g. if δ is a topogenous relation, what does AδB mean in terms of the corresponding closed subset of βX×βX?

    • CommentRowNumber13.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeDec 29th 2014

    I believe it means this: given a topogenous relation δ, consider the set

    {(𝒰,𝒱)βX×βX:((A,B)PX×PX)A𝒰B𝒱(A,B)δ}.

    This is a closed subset of βX×βX. For example, take δ to be the minimal topogenous relation, consisting of (A,B) such that AB. I claim the corresponding closed subset is the diagonal of βX×βX. Any point (𝒰,𝒰) certainly belongs to the subset, since A𝒰 and B𝒰 implies AB𝒰, so necessarily AB. On the other hand, if 𝒰 and 𝒱 are distinct ultrafilters, then we can find an A𝒰 for which A𝒱, so that A𝒰 and ¬A𝒱. Then if (𝒰,𝒱) belongs to the closed set, we reach the conclusion (A,¬A)δ or A¬A, a contradiction.

    (I’ll probably add more to this response in a while; have to run now.)

    • CommentRowNumber14.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeDec 29th 2014
    • (edited Dec 29th 2014)

    Continuing the previous post: let’s check that the subset Kδ of βX×βX corresponding to a topogenous relation δ is closed, as claimed. Suppose (𝒰,𝒱)Kδ, so that there exist A,BPX such that A𝒰 and B𝒱 and (A,B)δ. Then, letting [A] denote the basic clopen {𝒰:A𝒰}, it seems to be trivially true that the open set [A]×[B] contains (𝒰,𝒱) and does not intersect Kδ, so the subset is closed.

    So far we have not said anything about the conditions for δ to be a topogenous relation; we do know that Kδ contains the diagonal if δ contains all pairs (A,B) that intersect in a nonempty set. So let’s go in the opposite direction: starting from a closed reflexive relation KβX×βX, produce a corresponding topogenous relation δK. It seems clear what to do: define

    δK{(A,B)PX×PX:([A]×[B])K}.

    Let’s see: the map PXPβX mapping A to [A] is a Boolean algebra map and therefore preserves joins, and the operations ×[B] and K also preserve joins, and one pretty quickly concludes from there that the conditions for δK to be a topogenous relation are met.

    We should go on and check that δKδ is inverse to KδK, giving a covariant bijection between topogenous relations and reflexive relations on βX. I think I’ll skip this for now (I’m reasonably confident).

    • CommentRowNumber15.
    • CommentAuthorMike Shulman
    • CommentTimeDec 30th 2014

    Ok, this is starting to make sense. If we think of points of βX as “ideal points” of X, then Kδ is the “ideal set” of all points (x,y) such that every pair of sets Ax and By are δ-related. Except that we have to allow x,y to be in βX rather than X for this to retain enough information.

    That makes me wonder what topogenous relations look like in nonstandard analysis. The obvious thing would be to consider the analogous subset of *X×*X, the pairs (x,y) such that if x*A and y*B then AδB. This gives a reflexive (external) relation δ on nonstandard points of X. Does this relation retain all the information about δ? Can one characterize the external relations which arise from topogenous relations?

    • CommentRowNumber16.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeDec 30th 2014
    • (edited Dec 30th 2014)

    So okay, I might as well go ahead and establish the bijection mentioned in my last message. It will simplify things a bit if we drop the reflexivity from both sides, and just concentrate on conditions 2 and 3 for a topogenous relation (I call such a thing a topogeny), and similarly on the β side drop the reflexivity. It will also work more smoothly if I set up a Galois connection between complements of topogenies (call them antitopogenies) and closed sets of βX×βX. I’ll remark that if δ is an antitopogeny, then (A,B)δ and (A,B)δ together implies (AA,B)δ, and similarly in the second argument; also sets (,B) and (A,) belong to δ.

    So, we set up a relation RPX×PX×βX×βX where (A,B,𝒰,𝒱)R if ¬A𝒰 or ¬B𝒱. This induces a Galois connection in the usual way, where given a subset δPX×PX we consider

    δR{(𝒰,𝒱):((A,B)δ)R(A,B,𝒰,𝒱)}

    which is an intersection of basic closed sets ¬([A]×[B]) with (A,B) ranging over δ, hence closed. And given a subset KβX×βX we consider

    KR{(A,B):((𝒰,𝒱)K)R(A,B,𝒰,𝒱)}

    which is an intersection of antitopogenous relations ¬(𝒰×𝒱), hence antitopogenous. With the Galois connection infrastructure in place, it’s enough to show that (1) every closed set of βX×βX is of the form Kδ for some δPX×PX, and (2) every antitopogeny is of the form δK for some KβX×βX. (1) is trivial since every closed K is an intersection of basic closed sets of the form ¬([A]×[B]) (i.e., the basic open sets are [A]×[B]), so just take those (A,B) we need to form the set δ. (2) is an application of the ultrafilter lemma. I won’t go through all the details, but if δPX×PX is an antitopogeny, then the collection of sets (A,0)δ is an ideal and is contained in a maximal ideal, and furthermore one has sufficiently many such maximal ideals (i.e., every ideal is the intersection of the maximal ideals ¬𝒰 containing it). Similarly sets of the form (0,B) form an ideal which is the intersection of sufficiently many maximal ideals, and one can work out that any antitopogeny is an intersection of sets of the form {(A,B):A𝒰orB𝒱} where 𝒰,𝒱 range over sufficiently many ultrafilters.

    In fact, I’m going to add the remark now to syntopogenous space that every topogeny is a union of “basic topogenies” which are those of the form 𝒰×𝒱PX×PX, a cartesian product of ultrafilters.

    • CommentRowNumber17.
    • CommentAuthorMike Shulman
    • CommentTimeDec 17th 2016

    At syntopogenous space I wrote as the definition:

    • For any δ𝒪, there exists a δ𝒪 such that if A,BX have the property that whenever CD=X, either AδC or BδD, then AδB.

    But now that seems wrong to me: instead of BδD it should be DδB. That’s what we have in the corresponding condition at proximity space, and that’s the only way I can see to make (for instance) the identification of topological spaces with simple perfect syntopogenies true. So I’ve fixed it. I no longer have Császár’s book in front of me, but I suspect I translated incorrectly from his use of instead of δ. (Actually, it would be nice to rewrite the page treating δ,, on an equal footing the way we do at proximity space.)

    • CommentRowNumber18.
    • CommentAuthorMike Shulman
    • CommentTimeDec 29th 2016

    I added some more remarks to syntopogenous space about and and how things behave constructively.

    • CommentRowNumber19.
    • CommentAuthorMike Shulman
    • CommentTimeFeb 6th 2017

    Coming back and re-reading Todd’s page on topogenies, it’s clear from the positioning of negations that constructively, the definition using is the most natural. This was also the way Császár originally phrased it; I now regret that I originally wrote syntopogenous space in terms of δ relations instead. Specifically, what Császár calls “topogenous orders” are what Todd calls “flat profunctors”, whose composites are simply relational composites. Moreover, a simple syntopogeny (i.e. a quasi-proximity) is just a comonoid in the bicategory of such profunctors, and an arbitrary syntopogeny should be obtainable similarly from its local ind-completion.

    Why a comonoid? It seems related to the observation that apartness relations are the open complements, in a discrete locale, of closed equivalence relations, so that their “comparison” axiom is more like a comultiplication than a multiplication. So I am wondering whether the characterizations of topogenies and relational beta-modules in terms of the ultrafilter space β could constructively be rephrased using the localic Stone-Cech compactification, whose frame of opens is directly related to ideals and filters without needing to pass through the ultrafilters (its points, of which constructively there may not be enough). Perhaps this would yield the corresponding “apartness” notions.

    However, I’m currently a bit stuck on the constructive counterpart of Todd’s Proposition 4.10 with its slick use of Stone duality. I think if we remove the dualizations, then the result ought to be that opens in βX1××βXn correspond to separately join-preserving maps PX1××PXnΩop (or perhaps some subclass of these satisfying a “decomposability” property dual to complete regularity). The latter in the case n=2 would be the version of a topogenous relation, so that its complement “δ” would be a closed sublocale. Separately join-preserving maps PX1××PXnΩop should still correspond to ideals in the distributive lattice PX1PXn, but where do we go from there?

    • CommentRowNumber20.
    • CommentAuthorMike Shulman
    • CommentTimeFeb 6th 2017

    Hmm, now I am getting a glimmer. There are actually two, or maybe three, different compactifications hiding under the name β. Namely, for any locale X, we can construct:

    • The locale K0(X) with O(K0(X))=Idl(X), the frame of ideals in X (which is the free frame on the underlying distributive lattice of X)
    • The locale K2(X) with O(K2(X)) the frame of “completely regular” ideals (those for which any UI is some VI, where is the “very inside” relation of complete regularity)
    • The locale K1(X), which is like K2(X) but using “strongly regular” ideals instead, for which is the finest interpolating relation contained in the “well-inside” relation of regularity

    Countable choice gives K1(X)=K2(X). Moreover, if O(X) is a Boolean algebra (such as if excluded middle holds and X is discrete), then K0(X)=K1(X)=K2(X) too, since in a Boolean algebra every element is very-inside itself. In general, K1(X) or K2(X) is the “Stone-Cech compactification” β; but I suspect that when applying β to discrete spaces/locales as we do when defining relational β-modules and so on, constructively we may be more interested in K0(X).

    In particular, while K1 and K2 are reflections into the full subcategories of compact regular and compact completely-regular locales, K0 is a non-idempotent monad on Loc; it is dual to the comonad on Frm induced by the free-forgetful adjunction to DLat. So it seems more likely to give an interesting notion of generalized multicategory.

    • CommentRowNumber21.
    • CommentAuthorMike Shulman
    • CommentTimeFeb 9th 2017

    To start with, here is a constructive proof of Todd’s theorem that topogenies from X to Y correspond to closed subspaces of βX×βY. Constructively, I will dualize both the topogenies and the subspaces, and prove that topogenous apartnesses from X to Y (relations between subsets of X and Y such that ABC(ACBC) and C and dually) correspond to open sublocales of K0X×K0Y, where O(K0(X))=Idl(P(X)) as above. (Note that the strongly closed sublocales are exactly the duals of the open ones, though this is not true for spaces constructively.)

    By definition of locale products as suplattice tensor products, the opens in K0X×K0Y are formal joins of tensor products of an ideal in P(X) with an ideal in P(Y), modulo an equivalence relation making the tensor product distribute over joins in both variables. In one direction, given a topogenous apartness , we send it to the join of tensor products of principal ideals AB(A)(B). In the other direction, given an open i(JiKi), we define AB to mean A=A1An and B=B1Bm where for each j,k there is an i such that AjJi and BkKi.

    To show that these are inverses, starting from , if A=A1An and B=B1Bm and for each j,k there exist principal ideals (C) and (D) with AjC and BkD and CD, then also AjBk by isotony, hence AB by finite additivity of . (And obviously, if AB then A(A) and B(B).)

    On the other side, since any ideal is the directed join of the principal ideals it contains (directed joins of ideals are just unions) and distributes over joins, any open is equivalent to a join of tensor products i(Ci)(Di) of tensor products of principal ideals. Then each CiDi in the resulting apartness , hence (Ci)(Di) appears in the open reconstructed from it. Conversely, if AB, then A=A1An and B=B1Bm and for each j,k there exists an ij,k with AjCij,k and BkDij,k. Then by definition of the finite join of ideals, the ideal J=j,k(Cij,k) contains A and the ideal K=j,k(Dij,k) contains B, and the tensor product JK might as well appear in the given open since distributes over joins, hence so might as well also (A)(B).

    A similar, but simpler, argument shows that opens in X×K0(Y) correspond to point-set apartness relations xA for xX and AY satisfying isotony and finite additivity on the right.

    • CommentRowNumber22.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeFeb 9th 2017

    I haven’t read through this properly yet, but this sounds awesome!

    I never tried to consider the constructive aspects while writing the topogeny stuff up, because the stuff I was trying to reinterpret seemed so inundated with excluded middle in the first place (and I felt sure the guy I was communicating with at the time would not be the least interested). So I’m glad you’re taking this up.

    • CommentRowNumber23.
    • CommentAuthorMike Shulman
    • CommentTimeFeb 10th 2017

    Perhaps it’s better to consider the opens in K0X×K0Y as (-1)-sheaves for a coverage, the way Johnstone does it. Then they are sets 𝒥 of tensor products JK, where JIdl(P(X)) and KIdl(P(Y)), such that

    1. if J2K2𝒥 and J1J2 and K1K2, then J1K1𝒥 (presheaf)
    2. if JiK𝒥 for all i then (iJi)K𝒥 and dually, where iJi={A1An each Ai belongs to some Ji} (sheaf)

    With this representation, the apartness relation corresponding to an open 𝒥 says that AB if (A)(B)𝒥, and the open corresponding to an apartness relation is {JKAJ,BK,AB}. The bijection between the two is then even easier.

    • CommentRowNumber24.
    • CommentAuthorMike Shulman
    • CommentTimeFeb 10th 2017

    Now I claim that just like apartness relations are exactly closed equivalence relations on a discrete locale, decomposable proximal (set-set) apartnesses are exactly closed equivalence relations on K0X for a discrete locale X (and similarly decomposable quasi-proximal apartnesses correspond to closed preorders). The above argument shows that closed sublocales of K0X×K0X correspond to set-set relations satisfying the appropriate isotony and additivity properties, and the correspondence of symmetry is clear; so it suffices to consider reflexivity and decomposable transitivity.

    For reflexivity, the diagonal is contained in a closed sublocale CU of K0X×K0X iff U is contained in the exterior of the diagonal, which is the largest open whose restriction along the diagonal is 0. As a (-1)-sheaf, this exterior is the set of all JK such that JK=0. Thus, CU contains the diagonal iff AB implies AB=0, which is the proximal reflexivity axiom.

    Transitivity of CU means that the pullback π*2U is contained in π*1Uπ*3U as open subsets of K0X×K0X×K0X. If U corresponds to , then we have

    π*1U={JKLBK,CL,BC}
    π*2U={JKLAJ,CL,AC}
    π*3U={JKLAJ,BK,AB}

    The tricky thing is π*1Uπ*3U, since it is not just the union of these sets but the (-1)-sheafification of the union. However, I claim that

    π*1Uπ*3U={JKLAJ,BK,CL,D,E,(ADECB=DE}

    It’s easy to see that this is a (-1)-sheaf, and that it contains π*1U and π*3U. Moreover, every JKL in this set can be obtained from those in π*1U and π*3U by three steps of gluing:

    JKL=AJ((A)KL)=AJCL((A)K(C))=AJCL((A)KA(C))AJCL((A)KC(C))

    where KA={DKAD} and KC={EKEC}, so that (A)KA(C)π*3U and (A)KC(C)π*1U. The final decomposition as a binary join uses the assumed property of JKL and the fact that joins of ideals are computed by taking finite joins of their elements. Thus, the above set of triples of ideals is a (-1)-sheaf containing π*1U and π*3U and contained in the sheafification of their union, so it must be their join as (-1)-sheaves.

    Now transitivity π*2Uπ*1Uπ*3U is equivalent to the special case that each triple of the form (A)(X)(C), with AC, is an element of the above set. This means exactly that whenever AC there are sets D,E such that AD and EC and X=DE, the decomposability axiom for a proximal apartness.

    • CommentRowNumber25.
    • CommentAuthorMike Shulman
    • CommentTimeFeb 10th 2017

    None of this actually requires X to be discrete. However, if we allow X to be non-discrete, then there should be some compatibility condition on a proximity, such as that every AO(X) satisfies A={BO(X)C,AC=XBC}. I’m not sure yet how to interpret that in terms of a closed equivalence relation.

    However, K0X has the interesting property that any map f:XY with Y compact Hausdorff (i.e. compact regular) factors through a map g:K0XY defined by g*(W)={AO(X)Af*W}, where is the well-inside relation of regularity. I don’t think g is unique, and while K0X itself is compact and contains X densely, it is not Hausdorff — but quotienting it by a closed equivalence relation seems like a natural way to make it Hausdorff! Certainly the kernel pair of a Hausdorff quotient is a closed equivalence relation, so that if an effective equivalence relation has a Hausdorff quotient then it is closed. Dually, if a closed equivalence relation is effective, then the quotient map is proper, and since closed sublocales descend along proper maps it follows that the quotient is Hausdorff. Thus, the effective closed equivalence relations on K0X correspond bijectively to quotients of K0X that are Hausdorff, giving a locale-theoretic approach to the standard bijective correspondence between proximities and compactifications.

    This suggests strongly that effectiveness should correspond to the above compatibility condition on proximities. However, I don’t know how to show this because I don’t know a characterization of which equivalence relations in Loc are effective.

    • CommentRowNumber26.
    • CommentAuthorMike Shulman
    • CommentTimeFeb 10th 2017

    Oh, that’s silly – the compatibility condition doesn’t mean Hausdorffness of the quotient, it means that the composite map from X to the quotient is a sublocale embedding. Maybe the quotient is always Hausdorff. I think I can show that it does look like other definitions of the compactification of a proximity locale.