Not signed in (Sign In)

Not signed in

Want to take part in these discussions? Sign in if you have an account, or apply for one below

  • Sign in using OpenID

Site Tag Cloud

2-category 2-category-theory abelian-categories adjoint algebra algebraic algebraic-geometry algebraic-topology analysis analytic-geometry arithmetic arithmetic-geometry book bundles calculus categorical categories category category-theory chern-weil-theory cohesion cohesive-homotopy-type-theory cohomology colimits combinatorics complex complex-geometry computable-mathematics computer-science constructive cosmology deformation-theory descent diagrams differential differential-cohomology differential-equations differential-geometry digraphs duality elliptic-cohomology enriched fibration foundation foundations functional-analysis functor gauge-theory gebra geometric-quantization geometry graph graphs gravity grothendieck group group-theory harmonic-analysis higher higher-algebra higher-category-theory higher-differential-geometry higher-geometry higher-lie-theory higher-topos-theory homological homological-algebra homotopy homotopy-theory homotopy-type-theory index-theory integration integration-theory internal-categories k-theory lie-theory limits linear linear-algebra locale localization logic mathematics measure measure-theory modal modal-logic model model-category-theory monad monads monoidal monoidal-category-theory morphism motives motivic-cohomology nlab noncommutative noncommutative-geometry number-theory of operads operator operator-algebra order-theory pages pasting philosophy physics pro-object probability probability-theory quantization quantum quantum-field quantum-field-theory quantum-mechanics quantum-physics quantum-theory question representation representation-theory riemannian-geometry scheme schemes set set-theory sheaf simplicial space spin-geometry stable-homotopy-theory stack string string-theory superalgebra supergeometry svg symplectic-geometry synthetic-differential-geometry terminology theory topology topos topos-theory tqft type type-theory universal variational-calculus

Vanilla 1.1.10 is a product of Lussumo. More Information: Documentation, Community Support.

Welcome to nForum
If you want to take part in these discussions either sign in now (if you have an account), apply for one now (if you don't).
  1. Let me apologize for being extremely vague in formulating this question. If F: C --> D is a functor, its left derived functor LF (if it exists) is the right Kan extension of F along the projection C --> Ho(C). Yet, I could think of weak equivalences on C as a first approximation of an (infinity,1)-category structure on C, which I will denote C(infinity) just to fix the notations, and the functor F as a functor between quasi-categories N(F): N(C) --> N(D), where N denotes the nerve. Since C(infinity) is roughtly obtained from C by adding more cells in addition to commutative diagrams, I expect to have a natural inclusion functor N(C) --> C(infinity), and I can wonder about the existence of a right Kan extension of N(F) along the inclusion. This should, at least naively, correspond to taking the best infinity-approximation of F, and I'd like to think to it as a version of LF which "remembers" all higher homotopies. How far is this way of thinking from being correct?
    • CommentRowNumber2.
    • CommentAuthorMike Shulman
    • CommentTimeDec 8th 2009

    It seems to me that it should be mostly correct. A Kan extension of N(F) itself along N(C) \to C(\infty) will factor through the quotient map C(\infty) \to N(Ho(C)), since N(D) is an ordinary category, and therefore it will be just (the nerve of) the ordinary derived functor of F composed with the quotient map C(\infty) \to N(Ho(C)), and thus not containing any "higher information". But probably what you really want is to take the Kan extension of the composite N(C) \to N(D) \to D(\infty) along N(C)\to C(\infty); that ought to remember the higher homotopies. But I don't know whether this is written down anywhere.

    • CommentRowNumber3.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeDec 8th 2009

    do I understand you correctly, that you want C(infinity) to denote the simplicial localization of the category with weak equivalences C?

    I suppose you have seen the query box discussion at derived functor?

    Allow me to assume that we have a bit more information than just weak equivalences available, namely a nice model category structure. Then the (oo,1)-category presented by C is the simplicial localization restricted to the cofibrant-fibrant objects (as described by the Dwyer-Kan theorem recalled by the big diagram at (infinity,1)-categorical hom-space).

    Typically the functors that are of interest respect this simplicial enrichement. As Mike desribes in the query box at derived functor, in that case the "correct" extension of F to the (oo,1)-category presented by C is its restriction as a simplicially enriched functor to the fibrant-cofibrant objects (or equivalently its precomposition with a fibrant-cofibrant replacement functor).

  2. thanks. I indeed had looked at the query box, but had been unable to read Mike's comment on the precomposition with fibrant-cofibrant replacements as an extension to the (oo,1)-category presented by C, which was precisely what I was aiming to. as far as concerns C(infty), by that I intended to mean the simplicial localization of the category with weak equivalences C, or -if that was needed in order to make things work- the (oo,1)-category presented by a model category structure on C. so Urs perfectly answer my question, and aslo Mike correctly interpret I was implicitly referring to the extension of N(C) --> D(oo) along N(C)--> C(oo).

    so, going back to the derived functor query box and summing up with what's written here, the situation should be as follows:

    i) one can define a notion of derived functor of F: C--> D as soon as a notion of homotopy category Ho(C), an so as soon one has a notion of weak equivalence. it is (if it exists) the Kan extension of F along C --> Ho(C).

    ii) in particular, when also D has weak equivalences one can consider the derived functor LF: Ho(C) --> Ho(D) whih is by definition the extension of the composition C --> D --> Ho(D) along C--> Ho(C) (if it exists)

    iii) this notion seems however to be too weak to be of concrete use (Mike's comment, if I don't misunderstand it), and the useful notion is obtained when C is a model category. In this case one can consider the extension of F to a functor F(oo): C(oo) --> D(oo). taking pi_0's one obtains LF:Ho(C) --> Ho(D).
    • CommentRowNumber5.
    • CommentAuthorMike Shulman
    • CommentTimeDec 9th 2009

    C doesn't have to be a model category in order to go to the infinity-case; any category with weak equivalences has a simplicial localization. What you need a model category for (or, more generally, a deformation retract of a homotopical category) is to define derived functors in the "useful" way as being given by precomposition with a "replacement" functor, rather than in the "un-useful" way as a Kan extension.

    • CommentRowNumber6.
    • CommentAuthorHarry Gindi
    • CommentTimeDec 9th 2009
    Kan extensions are "un-useful" in what way?
    • CommentRowNumber7.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeDec 9th 2009
    This comment is invalid XHTML+MathML+SVG; displaying source. <div> <blockquote> Kan extensions are "un-useful" in what way? </blockquote> <p>As a way of characterizing derived functors. See the query box discussion at <a href="https://ncatlab.org/nlab/show/derived+functor">derived functor</a>.</p> </div>
    • CommentRowNumber8.
    • CommentAuthorMike Shulman
    • CommentTimeDec 9th 2009

    If you know of any theorems about derived functors, defined as Kan extensions without making use of the fact that in good cases (such as model categories) they can be computed with fibrant/cofibrant replacement, or even of any theorem about a particular derived functor which uses the fact that it is a Kan extension, I'd be interested to hear it. The only thing I can think of which comes close is the fact that a given functor has at most one left derived functor, independent of whatever model structure you choose to compute it with, but that can also just as easily be proven directly.