Want to take part in these discussions? Sign in if you have an account, or apply for one below
Vanilla 1.1.10 is a product of Lussumo. More Information: Documentation, Community Support.
From theorem 1 proved in the page M-complete category follows that (⊥M,M) is a factorization system. Obviously M⊂(⊥M)⊥: they are equal whenever M is part of a prefactorization system. Can you give me an example of M where this inclusion is strict?
If you mean in the generality of “any class of maps M”, just consider M=∅. Then ⊥M is all maps and so (⊥M)⊥ is the isomorphisms.
Thank you. I always forget trivial examples.
I have another problem with the proof of theorem 2; both the final step in the original proof in [CHK] and the sentence “Passing to adjuncts again, we find that Sg is also split epic” seem rather cryptic. Can you spend a word on it?
Trying to mesh the two arguments, I’m left with this verification: Sg is an isomorphism. It’s clear that Sg is a split mono. If I follow [CHK] I’m left to prove that Sg is a split epic; to do this, [CHK] builds the pullback diagram
Qy→TSAx↓↓TSgX→ηXTSXand then proves that x is an isomorphism. Even if I take this for granted, how should I conclude that Sg admits a right inverse? If I pass to the adjunct of TSg∘y∘x−1=ηX I get εSX∘STSg∘Sy∘S(x−1)=1, from which the thesis follows when (for example) also εSX is invertible (by a retract-closure argument?).
I am confused also by this:
TSg is then also split monic, hence belongs to M and thus also to M′.
This seems not to be a general result (I wouldn’t have any idea why it should be true). Instead, it seems to follow from the fact that T(Sg)∈T(homC)⊂(⊥T(homC))⊥=MS. Right?
((Edit: I added some details to your proof, in the hope of having made it slightly clearer for the occasional reader; I hope you won’t mind!))
You seem to have answered our own questions. Although something seems to be missing from the second paragraph of your expanded proof.
You’re right, there were a couple of typos. Now it works fine!
I wanted to check every detail to see where I precisely needed that the class M in the definition of M-completeness is made by monomorphisms. Is there a similar notion of M-completeness for ∞-categories? Do I have to replace “monomorphisms” with something else, in that setting?
I want to compare the definition (“[…] We say that C is M-complete if it admits all (even large) intersections of M-subobjects”) with Lurie’s HTT.6.1.6 which says “in the ∞-categorical context the emphasis on subobjects misses the point”. In particular, I can define subobjects in an ∞-category as equivalence classes of (−1)-truncated morphisms, but I don’t see why this should be the right point ov view to define ∞-M-completeness.
The question doesn’t seem trivial, as far as I can see, since the hierarchy between monic arrows becomes rather blurred in ∞-categorical setting:
In higher category theory, we may still consider the notion of “split monomorphism”, i.e. a morphism m:A→B in C such that there exists a morphism r:B→A with r∘m being equivalent to the identity of A. However, in a higher category, such a morphism m will not necessarily be a “monomorphism”, that is, it need not be (−1)-truncated.
In general […] in an (∞,1)-category, a split mono is not necessarily truncated at any finite level.
An excellent question! I don’t know the answer.
It seems that the only (or the main) problem is to figure out which is the right definition of monomorphism we want to adopt; let’s mantain it in a vague sense and backwards-engineer to see which is the feature of a monic arrow we need.
A quasicategory endowed with a distinguished class 𝒦 of arrows is a marked simplicial set which happens to be a quasicategory. I denote with Mrk(C) the class of all markings of a fixed ∞-category C. This is a posetal class in the obvious sense.
Let now 𝒦 be a marking of C which is contained in the marking Mono of monomorphisms of C. We say that C is 𝒦-complete if it admits all (even large) intersections of 𝒦-objects, i.e. arbitrary (even large) limits of families {Xi→A}i∈J for any fixed object A∈C.
More precisely, whenever we can consider a diagram J→𝒦, where J is possibly a class (depending on the ontology we want to consider, this can be either a (discrete, if we think simplicially) set outside of a universe ℧ fixed once and for all at the beginning of the discussion, or a proper class in NBG), then we can form the (∞-)limit lim{Xi→A}i∈J in the ∞-category of arrows 𝒦/A⊆C/A.
This is a tentative to rephrase the first result:
Let C be a quasicategory and 𝒦∈Mrk(C) a marking such that
- C is 𝒦-complete;
- 𝒦 is closed under composition, pullbacks and is contained in the marking Mono∈Mrk(C).
Then the pair of markings (⊥𝒦,𝒦) is a factorization system on C.
And this is a tentative rephrasing of the second:
Let S⊣T:A⇆C an (∞-)adjunction, 𝒦∈Mrk(C) a class of monics which contains all the split monics. Let A be 𝒦-complete in the former sense. Then, if we consider the prefactorization 𝔽 right-generated by T(C1) (i.e. (⊥(T(C1)),(⊥(T(C1)))⊥), we have
- ⊥(T(C1))=Σ(S);
- 𝔽 is a factorization system.
(I’m being sloppy, but the things I didn’t define properly are easily adapted to the ∞-categorical setting.)
The proof of the first statement should go the same way than the classical one: consider an arrow f:[1]→C and the class J𝒦(f) of all objects in C admitting a 𝒦-arrow to the codomain of f, through which f factors, i.e. all the commutative triangles f=mp, where m:X→B belongs to 𝒦.
This can be seen as a diagram J𝒦(f)→C[2], whose composition with d*0:C[2]→C[1] gives a diagram J𝒦(f)→𝒦. Now, since C is 𝒦-complete, we can consider the wide pullback of all these arrows, and the universal property of this limit gives a factorization of f.
It remains to show that p∈E=⊥𝒦: to do this, we consider the same lifting problem, do the same pullback, and obtain the same factorization p=nj, with j∈𝒦. Now, mn is a 𝒦-arrow through which f factors, hence there must be b such that mnb=m; here the nature of the flavour in which we interpret the word “monomorphism” becomes important.
If you mean in the generality of “any class of maps M”, just consider M=∅. Then ⊥M is all maps and so (⊥M)⊥ is the isomorphisms.
Returning on this, I am confused (and I posed a confuesd question). If in the end we prove that (E,M) is a factorization, it must in particular be a prefactorization, so that M=E⊥=(⊥M)⊥. So what prevents me from having M=(⊥M)⊥ in general? M=∅ obviously misses condition 3, like any other counterexample I can think about.
My original question should have been posed like this: there can’t be a M satisfying 1,2,3,4 of Thm 1 without being equal to (⊥M)⊥. So isn’t it true that I can prove WLOG the Corollary (which follows Thm 1), supposing that M+1,2,3,4 is part of a prefactorization system?
I don’t understand the question. If M satisfies 1,2,3,4 of Theorem 1, then by Theorem 1 it is part of a factorization system, hence also part of a prefactorization system.
My intuition finds rather surprising that 1,2,3,4 ⇒M=(⊥M)⊥; I think it’s me, I don’t see something obvious. So nevermind. Since you liked the question, I worked out some more details: I’m able to reproduce the results in that page if “monomorphism” is replaced with “monic arrow” in the sense of Joyal notes: an edge f:[1]→C is a monic in the q∞-category C if the square
S1→S1↓↓fS→fTis a homotopy limit. The next step is extend once more, ∞-izing the result in
D. Zangurashvili, Factorization systems and adjunctions, Georgian Mathematical Journal. Volume 6, Issue 2, Pages 191–200.
which says that
If F:C⇆X:U is a reflection and X is 𝒦-complete, then for any (E,M) factorization system in X we have a factorization system
(F−1E∘,(⊥U(M∘))⊥)[to be completed…]
Ah, so maybe the real question is, why in the definition of orthogonal factorization system does one not need to include the assumptions M=(⊥M)⊥ and E=⊥(E⊥) (or equivalently that E and M are closed under retracts)? (E.g. they are omitted from the third definition given on the page orthogonal factorization system.) That is a bit surprising, and I don’t even remember off the top of my head why it’s true.
There seems to be a typo in [CHK]. The functoriality of factorisations is implied by E⊆⊥M (or equivalently M⊆E⊥), not the other inclusion. And once we have functorial unique factorisation, to determine whether a morphism is in E (or M) it suffices to examine its functorial unique factorisation.
A more symmetric notation for E⊆⊥M and M⊆E⊥ is “E⊥M”.
1 to 14 of 14