Want to take part in these discussions? Sign in if you have an account, or apply for one below
Vanilla 1.1.10 is a product of Lussumo. More Information: Documentation, Community Support.
1 to 21 of 21
What is the definition of an infinity-stack on an infinity-site with values in an arbitrary infinity-category (bicomplete, say)? The definition I know works only for stacks of infinity-groupoids.
Maybe this: is a stack/sheaf iff is a sheaf for all objects ?
That’s reasonable, at least for categories of structures “defined by finite (homotopy) limits”.
Zhen Lin: what does that mean? (At the moment I’m interested in stacks of infinity-categories.)
DAGV says, for X a topos, a C-valued sheaf is a limit preserving functor X^op —> C, for any arbitrary C.
Dylan: that definition doesn’t take into account the topology on the site though. Oh wait, X is already a topos. I’m confused now…
Well, going back to ordinary examples, we know that a “sheaf of local rings” is not actually defined to be a sheaf taking values in local rings in this sense. But otherwise the obvious thing works well for many examples: groups, rings, etc. These are structures “defined by finite limits”. See sketch. I expect the same holds true for “homotopical” structures.
Dylan: that definition doesn’t take into account the topology on the site though. Oh wait, X is already a topos. I’m confused now…
It’s secretly the same as your definition. The idea is that every limit preserving functor is representable.
Right, of course, thanks to both of you. Perhaps this should go on the page infinity-stack.
Each definition has an advantage over the other though. On the one hand, one can speak of -valued sheaves on (∞,1)-topoi that don’t arise from a site. On the other hand, one can have -valued sheaves on that do not lift to (if doesn’t have enough limits).
The definition recalled in #5 is to be thought of as giving sheaves (stacks) on the topos regarded as a big site equipped with the canonical topology.
@Urs: one might think about it this way, but it doesn’t actually work for a general (∞,1)-topos.
Sorry, say again: what doesn’t work?
The Yoneda embedding is only an equivalence if is a sheaf (∞,1)-topos.
Where by “sheaf -topos” you mean topological localization of presheaves, I suppose.
I’d still think that for #6 this clarifies what’s going on, conceptually. Hypercompletion may probably be brought into the picture nicely somehow?
I was wondering about this also, and I’m not sure. That’s what the notion of “hypertopology” on a category would accomplish, I guess.
So, what’s the conclusion? Is it true that a functor is representable if and only if it is a sheaf for the canonical topology? This MO question remains unresolved.
Is this a correct argument? An (∞,1)-topos is the union of its subcategories of -compact objects for all cardinals such that is -accessible and closed under finite limits:
So
A presheaf on is a sheaf iff its restrictions to all ’s are sheaves, since every Cech nerve in is in for some . Hence
That seems correct, modulo the question of whether a sheaf for the canonical topology on necessarily satisfies descent for Čech nerves in . But that’s just a question of what the definition of canonical topology is, I guess.
Right, I was thinking of the topology on induced by epimorphic covers (in the topos ), so the canonical topology in the sense of HTT. Actually, do we even know that ?
Oh, sorry. I think I had some wires crossed. Yes, it would suffice to check that . In view of the fact that every limit-preserving functor is representable, it suffices to verify that the right Kan extension of a sheaf along the inclusion preserves limits. By accessibility, it should be enough to verify that a sheaf preserves limits for -small diagrams. But is this really any easier than the question we started with?
It doesn’t seem any easier, no. Let me list some facts which I think we know for sure:
is the identity. So is even a retract of .
1 to 21 of 21