Not signed in (Sign In)

Not signed in

Want to take part in these discussions? Sign in if you have an account, or apply for one below

  • Sign in using OpenID

Site Tag Cloud

2-category 2-category-theory abelian-categories adjoint algebra algebraic algebraic-geometry algebraic-topology analysis analytic-geometry arithmetic arithmetic-geometry book bundles calculus categorical categories category category-theory chern-weil-theory cohesion cohesive-homotopy-type-theory cohomology colimits combinatorics complex complex-geometry computable-mathematics computer-science constructive cosmology deformation-theory descent diagrams differential differential-cohomology differential-equations differential-geometry digraphs duality elliptic-cohomology enriched fibration foundation foundations functional-analysis functor gauge-theory gebra geometric-quantization geometry graph graphs gravity grothendieck group group-theory harmonic-analysis higher higher-algebra higher-category-theory higher-differential-geometry higher-geometry higher-lie-theory higher-topos-theory homological homological-algebra homotopy homotopy-theory homotopy-type-theory index-theory integration integration-theory k-theory lie-theory limits linear linear-algebra locale localization logic mathematics measure-theory modal modal-logic model model-category-theory monad monads monoidal monoidal-category-theory morphism motives motivic-cohomology nforum nlab noncommutative noncommutative-geometry number-theory of operads operator operator-algebra order-theory pages pasting philosophy physics pro-object probability probability-theory quantization quantum quantum-field quantum-field-theory quantum-mechanics quantum-physics quantum-theory question representation representation-theory riemannian-geometry scheme schemes set set-theory sheaf sheaves simplicial space spin-geometry stable-homotopy-theory stack string string-theory superalgebra supergeometry svg symplectic-geometry synthetic-differential-geometry terminology theory topology topos topos-theory tqft type type-theory universal variational-calculus

Vanilla 1.1.10 is a product of Lussumo. More Information: Documentation, Community Support.

Welcome to nForum
If you want to take part in these discussions either sign in now (if you have an account), apply for one now (if you don't).
    • CommentRowNumber1.
    • CommentAuthorThomas Holder
    • CommentTimeJul 18th 2015

    This is just a pointer to the recent tac paper from Lawvere and Menni on “Internal choice holds in the discrete part of any cohesive topos satisfying stable connected codiscreteness”.

    • CommentRowNumber2.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeJul 18th 2015

    thanks. I have added the pointer

    • William Lawvere, Matías Menni, Internal choice holds in the discrete part of any cohesive topos satisfying stable connected codiscreteness, Theory and Applications of Categories, Vol. 30, 2015, No. 26, pp 909-932. (TAC)

    to double negation topology, to cohesive topos and to Aufhebung

    • CommentRowNumber3.
    • CommentAuthorMike Shulman
    • CommentTimeJul 19th 2015

    Thanks. I would like to understand this paper, but right now I can’t make much of it: it reads like a long string of unmotivated technical definitions. If anyone has the time to make their way through it and write a gloss that includes motivation and examples, I would enjoy reading it.

    • CommentRowNumber4.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeJul 19th 2015
    • (edited Jul 19th 2015)

    Not sure if you saw the nLab paragraph I added before the Lab went down, this is the point that concerns what we had discussed here before re double negation and it culminates in 4.1-4.4:

    1) pieces-have-points implies initial Aufhebung \sharp \emptyset \simeq \emptyset,

    2) the converse follows if the \sharp-base is Boolean

    and hence in summary

    3) for cohesion over a Boolean base, pieces-have-points is equivalent to \sharp being double negation localization.

    • CommentRowNumber5.
    • CommentAuthorMike Shulman
    • CommentTimeJul 20th 2015

    Paragraph on what page?

    • CommentRowNumber6.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeJul 20th 2015

    Sorry for being unclear, I had announced that in a separate thread. But it’s just a tiny remark that I had added, now we have already spent more keystrokes on it than it may be worth it:

    I have added the statement of lemmas 4.1, 4.2 of Menni-Lawvere to cohesive topos here and to points-to-pieces transform here.

    • CommentRowNumber7.
    • CommentAuthorMike Shulman
    • CommentTimeJul 21st 2015

    Ah, thanks. That helps me know what to look for, at least.

    • CommentRowNumber8.
    • CommentAuthorMike Shulman
    • CommentTimeJul 21st 2015

    Is this true in the ∞-case too?

    • CommentRowNumber9.
    • CommentAuthorMike Shulman
    • CommentTimeJul 21st 2015

    I think it is. This is very nice! It means that for classical real-cohesion I don’t need to assume =\sharp\emptyset=\emptyset as an additional axiom. And it’s intriguing how we can use ʃ to give us information about \sharp.

    • CommentRowNumber10.
    • CommentAuthorMike Shulman
    • CommentTimeJul 21st 2015

    Here’s another question: what can we say about the composite ʃʃ\circ \sharp?

    • CommentRowNumber11.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeJul 21st 2015
    • (edited Jul 21st 2015)

    I think it is.

    That’s neat. Unfortunately I have no leisure for this right now. So what exactly do you think goes through? The full higher analog of both lemmas?

    what can we say about the composite ʃ∘♯?

    While I don’t know, intuitively I’d expect this to be contractible. In smooth cohesion it is known now that ʃX is given by lim[Δ smth ,X]\underset{\rightarrow}{\lim}[\Delta_{smth}^\bullet, X]. And I’d expect that lim[Δ smth ,X]*\underset{\rightarrow}{\lim}[\Delta_{smth}^\bullet, \sharp X] \simeq \ast. But I haven’t really thought about it any further.

    • CommentRowNumber12.
    • CommentAuthorMike Shulman
    • CommentTimeJul 21st 2015

    Lemma 4.1 makes perfect sense higher categorically if by “Nullstellensatz” one means pieces have points. I think Lemma 4.2 works fine too, but what it proves is that discrete objects are closed under subobjects. The equivalence of those is trickier, if nothing else trickier to track down (their Lemma 3.1 combined with Lemma 2.3 from Johnstone’s paper and A4.6.6 from the Elephant), but right now I think it should still be true. I think one can only obtain that AA\flat A \to A is mono when AA is 0-truncated (and one shouldn’t expect more), but I think that should be enough since surjectivity is detected by the 0-truncation.

    • CommentRowNumber13.
    • CommentAuthorMike Shulman
    • CommentTimeJul 21st 2015
    • (edited Jul 22nd 2015)

    I agree that intuitively ʃAʃ \sharp A should be contractible as long as AA is inhabited. In general I’d expect ʃAʃ \sharp A to be A\Vert A \Vert, the propositional truncation. So far, I can prove in real-cohesion that ʃAʃ \sharp A is “conditionally connected”, i.e. x,y:ʃAx=y\prod_{x,y:ʃ \sharp A} \Vert x=y\Vert. I think the proof should work in smooth cohesion too; all it needs is that there is an object RR with two distinct points such that ʃRʃR is contractible.

    • CommentRowNumber14.
    • CommentAuthorMike Shulman
    • CommentTimeJul 22nd 2015

    Haha, now I see that this is exactly the other conditions that Lawvere and Menni are studying. Their “connected codiscreteness” (CC) says that ʃAʃ\sharp A is always subterminal, which in the presence of pieces-have-points is equivalent to it being A\Vert A\Vert. They also prove (due mainly to Johnstone) that it’s equivalent to ʃ2=1ʃ\sharp 2 = 1, but I haven’t inspected that proof for ∞-ization.