Not signed in (Sign In)

Not signed in

Want to take part in these discussions? Sign in if you have an account, or apply for one below

  • Sign in using OpenID

Site Tag Cloud

2-category 2-category-theory abelian-categories adjoint algebra algebraic algebraic-geometry algebraic-topology analysis analytic-geometry arithmetic arithmetic-geometry book bundles calculus categorical categories category category-theory chern-weil-theory cohesion cohesive-homotopy-type-theory cohomology colimits combinatorics complex complex-geometry computable-mathematics computer-science constructive cosmology deformation-theory descent diagrams differential differential-cohomology differential-equations differential-geometry digraphs duality elliptic-cohomology enriched fibration foundation foundations functional-analysis functor gauge-theory gebra geometric-quantization geometry graph graphs gravity grothendieck group group-theory harmonic-analysis higher higher-algebra higher-category-theory higher-differential-geometry higher-geometry higher-lie-theory higher-topos-theory homological homological-algebra homotopy homotopy-theory homotopy-type-theory index-theory integration integration-theory k-theory lie-theory limits linear linear-algebra locale localization logic mathematics measure-theory modal modal-logic model model-category-theory monad monads monoidal monoidal-category-theory morphism motives motivic-cohomology nforum nlab noncommutative noncommutative-geometry number-theory of operads operator operator-algebra order-theory pages pasting philosophy physics pro-object probability probability-theory quantization quantum quantum-field quantum-field-theory quantum-mechanics quantum-physics quantum-theory question representation representation-theory riemannian-geometry scheme schemes set set-theory sheaf sheaves simplicial space spin-geometry stable-homotopy-theory stack string string-theory superalgebra supergeometry svg symplectic-geometry synthetic-differential-geometry terminology theory topology topos topos-theory tqft type type-theory universal variational-calculus

Vanilla 1.1.10 is a product of Lussumo. More Information: Documentation, Community Support.

Welcome to nForum
If you want to take part in these discussions either sign in now (if you have an account), apply for one now (if you don't).
    • CommentRowNumber1.
    • CommentAuthorTobyBartels
    • CommentTimeJan 29th 2010

    I redesigned cycle category, as had been requested there for some time. I'm not sure if the discussion decided whether the first definition was even correct; that discussion is now towards the bottom of the page. I also incorporated material from the erstwhile separate category of cycles.

    • CommentRowNumber2.
    • CommentAuthorzskoda
    • CommentTimeJan 29th 2010
    • (edited Jan 29th 2010)

    I am still personally feeling against the name cycle category. One of Mike's counterarguments was that parallel term the category of simplices is used in another meaning (comma category Delta over X for fixed simplicial set X). But e.g. Goerss-Jardine's book calls "simplex category" of X what you call the category of simplices of X, and many others call (what nlab calls) simplex category, "category of combinatorial simplices" just for ephasis.

    • CommentRowNumber3.
    • CommentAuthorPeter Heinig
    • CommentTimeJul 12th 2017
    • (edited Jul 12th 2017)

    [technical note: chose this thread since the cycle category appears to be an example of a category isomorphic to its dual]

    Is there already an “official’ nLab term for category isomorphic to its opposite category?

    Do you agree that if not, we should create one (and an article for it)?

    Do you agree that, at the very minimum, one should add to cycle category that it is isomorphic to its dual?

    Do you know whether anyone anywhere has systematically distinguished

    (0) categories which are equivalent but not isomorphic to their duals

    from

    (1) categories which are isomorphic to their duals?

    (Or is the variant (0) moot for some reason?)

    Motivation is that currently I have a hard technical motivation to understand this better, and to have a large collection of examples available. (One has been mentioned above, another not-entirely-unimportant one is what is sometimes called the walking quiver, i.e., the four-morphism category with two parallel morphisms. I mean, that the latter is isomorphic to its dual is obvious, but that it is can be seen to have some larger significance, which to get into here would lead too far afield)

    • CommentRowNumber4.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeJul 12th 2017
    • (edited Jul 12th 2017)

    Some off-the-cuff reactions:

    What would be the compelling point of imposing an isomorphism F:C opCF: C^{op} \to C rather than just having an equivalence?

    Of course such isomorphisms crop up; notably an equivalence is an isomorphism if the categories involved are skeletal. But I’m not sure that’s really enough to make a special point of talking about the isomorphism version.

    Yes, I agree that it is good to point out that the cycle category is self-dual (which is how I would informally refer to the equivalence version of the notion), and we could even say isomorphic here since the cycle category as defined is skeletal.

    We don’t seem to have an entry “self-dual category” although there are stronger variations on this theme we talk about. One interesting situation is where the equivalence comes from a dualizing object, where we obtain a self-dual category in this sense. An example there is Pontryagin duality. Another is dagger-category (which is an “evil” concept). Both of these are “involutive” dualities (in an appropriate sense). Then there are more specialized concepts such as those discussed at self-dual object and star-autonomous category.

    I don’t know of discussions where people have distinguished, “systematically” or otherwise, (0) from (1) at this level of generality. I lean more toward the possibility that it is (1) that is “moot” (again, at this level of generality – less moot perhaps in e.g. the more specialized situation of dagger-categories).

    My lone opinion is that it might be okay to create an entry “self-dual category” defined as a category that admits an equivalence F:C opCF: C^{op} \to C – but I’d want also a fairly convincing example of such in the wild that is not of “involutive” type (it’s easy of course to create artificial examples).

    • CommentRowNumber5.
    • CommentAuthorMike Shulman
    • CommentTimeJul 12th 2017

    I don’t know whether this counts as “in the wild”, but suppose DD is an arbitrary category and consider the category CC of endofunctors F 0:DDF_0:D\to D that are part of an infinite string of adjunctions

    F 2F 1F 0F 1F 2 \cdots \dashv F_{-2} \dashv F_{-1} \dashv F_0 \dashv F_1 \dashv F_2 \dashv \cdots

    Since taking mates under adjunctions reverses the direction of transformations, the assignation F 0F 1F_0 \mapsto F_1 is a contravariant functor C opCC^{op}\to C, which has as an inverse equivalence F 0F 1F_0\mapsto F_{-1}. But it is not involutive, and in general doesn’t even have finite order.

    • CommentRowNumber6.
    • CommentAuthorMike Shulman
    • CommentTimeJul 12th 2017

    I would say that (1) is of interest for strict categories, which include the cycle category. I would say it’s also of interest if the auto-isomorphism is the identity on objects, since an isomorphism of this sort can be formulated “non-evilly” in the dependently typed language of categories without referring to equality of objects (it consists of functions C(x,y)C(y,x)C(x,y) \to C(y,x) preserving composition) — when we add involutivity to this we obtain exactly the notion of dagger-category. (I don’t know of any identity-on-objects contravariant automorphisms that are not involutive, but I haven’t really tried to find any.)

    So I support the idea of making a page self-dual category discussing both notions, these restricted situations under which (1) is “sensible”, and the fact that most naturally occurring examples seem to be involutive and what that means, as well as some obvious properties that don’t depend on involutivity such as “if a self-dual category is complete then it is cocomplete”.

    • CommentRowNumber7.
    • CommentAuthorPeter Heinig
    • CommentTimeJul 13th 2017

    One off-the-cuff reaction to:

    I would say it’s also of interest if the auto-isomorphism is the identity on objects, since an isomorphism of this sort can be formulated “non-evilly” in the dependently typed language of categories without referring to equality of objects

    and to

    when we add involutivity to this we obtain exactly the notion of dagger-category.

    This immediately reminds me of the fact that in (from what I know of) finite-digraph theory, digraphs DD isomorphic to the graph obtained by reversing each arc, are mostly studied with the additional stronger requirement that there be at least one isomorphism φ\varphi witnessing this which is an involution and does not fix any vertex of the graph. Such DD are called skew-symmetric.

    I have never asked myself why this much stronger notion of “digraph isomorphic to its own reverse graph” is (apparently) the more important. I will look into that matter. In a sense, this is an example of the “an A is more than just a B, it is a B together with a specified C” pattern within combinatorics (this pattern abounds in category theory, an example being “an adjunction is more than just a pair of adjoint functors, it is a pair of adjoint functors together with a specified unit and counit). Here we have “a skew-symmetric digraph is more than just a digraph isomorphic to its reversal, it is a digraph isomorphic to its reversal together with a specified fixed-point-free involution to witness the isomorphism. Maybe we are onto something real here.