Want to take part in these discussions? Sign in if you have an account, or apply for one below
Vanilla 1.1.10 is a product of Lussumo. More Information: Documentation, Community Support.
I added the definition of uniformly/almost located to located subspace, as well as attempted proofs that covert and compact subspaces of uniformly regular uniform spaces are uniformly located. Unfortunately covert sets and compact spaces — as opposed to compact locales — seem to be hard to come by constructively. It would be nice to have some more concrete examples. I also don’t know what to write for the “idea” section, nor what Toby had in mind for “topologically located”.
I found the definition of topological locatedness thanks to Google Books. It has a similar flavour to the uniform case. Also an Idea section.
Thanks! Topological locatedness seems very weak; in particular, singletons being topologically located is weaker than quasiregularity.
I’d like to see more examples of located and non-located subsets, as well as examples of what located subspaces are used for. Where should I be looking?
Well, Bishop uses metrically located subsets. A lot of hereditary properties fail in general but work for located subspaces: total boundedness comes to mind. Besides that, Section 7.3 of Troelstra & van Dalen seems to be readable on Google Books.
I’m no longer convinced that Bridges’ “almost located” is the most natural generalization of metric locatedness to uniform spaces. If we translate almost-locatedness into a metric space, it says that for any there exists an such that for any , either or . But here could be much smaller than , whereas metric locatedness says that for any and any , the same disjunction holds for all .
It seems to me that a more natural notion of uniform locatedness would be that for any entourages such that we have . Whereas Bridges’ condition is implied by metric locatedness, I believe this condition implies metric locatedness, taking and and for sufficiently small . Bridges’ counterexample showing that metric locatedness is not a uniform invariant means that this notion of uniform locatedness is strictly stronger than metric locatedness, since it implies metric locatedness with respect to all metrics inducing the same uniformity. Moreover, I think I can prove that if is uniformly located in this sense then so is for any entourage , since and if then .
Unfortunately, this condition is much too strong. If the points of the discrete uniform space are located in this sense, then LEM follows: let be the diagonal , and for any . This suggests that we should only require it when the entourages are themselves located in some sense, but that’s getting circular. Hmm. Maybe should be replaced by , so that “point are located” becomes trivial? But then the proof of “ located located” fails, which is what I really wanted.
Actually, I guess “ located located” should also only be expected when is located (if then), since if is a point and then is probably not located.
Have to go, so I’m posting this kind of half-baked, but maybe someone will have helpful thoughts…
Maybe we just want a base of entourages that has this property, recognizing that general entourages (being completely arbitrary supersets of basic entourages) can be unlocatably weird.
Yes, I thought of that too. By itself, it’s not as strong as what I wanted, e.g. if we use the base of entourages then we can’t conclude, for instance, that . Even requiring the base to be closed under doesn’t quite give this, but it might still give an interesting notion (and I think closure under is necessary for the step anyway).
This is again weaker than metric locatedness, which at the moment I’m inclined to regard as a good thing: in Bridges’ example one might object that the set is only “accidentally” located with respect to one metric, but in fact I think I would argue that this set should be located (the metric space in question is itself weird, but the subset of it doesn’t involve any additional weirdness), and so the freedom to “choose an appropriate metric” is a good thing.
It does still seem that “points are located” is an additional condition for this notion of locatedness, but at least it’s not an unreasonably strong condition. I hope it would be satisfied by all metrizable or even gaugeable uniform spaces, although closing the base up under makes that not totally obvious.
Hmm… maybe it is unreasonably strong. If ranges over a set of positive real numbers with infimum , then the closure under of the entourage base for a metric space consists of the sets
where . There are canonical inclusions whenever we have an order-preserving map such that for all . But even if an inclusion is of this form, I don’t see how to show or . Even in the simple case , we would be claiming that for any either there is a with and , or . We can say that either or , but in a general metric space there’s no reason the former should be “subdividable” into the existence of a .
1 to 8 of 8