Not signed in (Sign In)

Not signed in

Want to take part in these discussions? Sign in if you have an account, or apply for one below

  • Sign in using OpenID

Site Tag Cloud

2-category 2-category-theory abelian-categories adjoint algebra algebraic algebraic-geometry algebraic-topology analysis analytic-geometry arithmetic arithmetic-geometry book bundles calculus categorical categories category category-theory chern-weil-theory cohesion cohesive-homotopy-type-theory cohomology colimits combinatorics complex complex-geometry computable-mathematics computer-science constructive cosmology definitions deformation-theory descent diagrams differential differential-cohomology differential-equations differential-geometry digraphs duality elliptic-cohomology enriched fibration foundation foundations functional-analysis functor gauge-theory gebra geometric-quantization geometry graph graphs gravity grothendieck group group-theory harmonic-analysis higher higher-algebra higher-category-theory higher-differential-geometry higher-geometry higher-lie-theory higher-topos-theory homological homological-algebra homotopy homotopy-theory homotopy-type-theory index-theory integration integration-theory k-theory lie-theory limits linear linear-algebra locale localization logic mathematics measure-theory modal modal-logic model model-category-theory monad monads monoidal monoidal-category-theory morphism motives motivic-cohomology nforum nlab noncommutative noncommutative-geometry number-theory of operads operator operator-algebra order-theory pages pasting philosophy physics pro-object probability probability-theory quantization quantum quantum-field quantum-field-theory quantum-mechanics quantum-physics quantum-theory question representation representation-theory riemannian-geometry scheme schemes set set-theory sheaf simplicial space spin-geometry stable-homotopy-theory stack string string-theory superalgebra supergeometry svg symplectic-geometry synthetic-differential-geometry terminology theory topology topos topos-theory tqft type type-theory universal variational-calculus

Vanilla 1.1.10 is a product of Lussumo. More Information: Documentation, Community Support.

Welcome to nForum
If you want to take part in these discussions either sign in now (if you have an account), apply for one now (if you don't).
    • CommentRowNumber1.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeMay 29th 2017

    As a kind of supplement to Urs’s running topology series, I wrote an article colimits of normal spaces. Mainly I had wanted to write down a reasonably clean proof of the fact that CW-complexes are T 4T_4 spaces, in particular Hausdorff, as called for on the page CW-complexes are paracompact Hausdorff spaces, but working in slightly greater generality. There are a whole bunch of links to stick in, which I plan to get to.

    This page has taken me longer than I had first anticipated. Only after some struggle and reading around did I discover the power of the Tietze characterization of normality, which can be used to give a simple proof of the following general fact:

    If X,Y,ZX, Y, Z are normal and if h:XZh: X \to Z is a closed embedding and f:XYf: X \to Y a continuous map, the attachment space = pushout W=Y XZW = Y \cup_X Z is also normal.

    This doesn’t seem so easy to prove with one’s bare hands (i.e., just using the usual definition of normality and reasoning away)!

    Urs, after recent discussion with Richard about paracompactness, where do matters stand on the page CW-complexes are paracompact Hausdorff spaces? It would be nice to tie up whatever loose ends are still left hanging there.

    • CommentRowNumber2.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeMay 29th 2017
    • (edited May 29th 2017)

    Thanks, Todd!

    where do matters stand

    [edited:] So I have replaced the brute force proof for single cell attachment and added in the immediate corollary that countable CW-complexes are paracompact: here

    If you could improve on that situation that would be nice. Please feel free to edit the page!

    • CommentRowNumber3.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeMay 29th 2017
    • (edited May 29th 2017)

    By the way, is there any problem with the article Miyazaki 52?

    I haven’t really looked at it, but somehow it’s not being cited. In the MO-discussion here one person first pointed it out and then deleted that comment.

    (Maybe that’s just because the OP seems not to be asking about paracompactness of CW-complexes, which he seems to take for granted, but of that of spaces of the homotopy type of a CW-complex. On the other hand, he didn’t complain about Neil Strickland’s pointer to Fritsch-Piccinini 90, which was posted on the same day as the (deleted) pointer to Miyazaki 52.)

    • CommentRowNumber4.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeMay 29th 2017

    Yeah, that’s the kind of quick and clean and elegant argument that I really like (what you put in for countable CW-complexes)!

    I haven’t looked at Miyazaki either, but I will say that Fritsch-Piccinini is a fantastic reference. (That’s where I picked up on using the Tietze extension characterization that I mentioned.)

    • CommentRowNumber5.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeMay 30th 2017

    So just to let you know: I looked yesterday at some of the approaches to proving paracompactness of all CW-complexes. The approach via E. Michael’s selection theorem(s) seems attractive, and I think it has nPOV potential as well, but I want to understand it better. On the other hand, it may be worth contemplating the choice principles involved; the use of Zorn’s lemma by Michael may be overkill. Still weighing options.

    • CommentRowNumber6.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeMay 30th 2017

    Thanks, Todd. You are closing a real gap in the literature here. Not regarding the result, of course, but regarding a decent proof of it.

    • CommentRowNumber7.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeMay 30th 2017

    Well, I am gradually becoming convinced that a completely parallel story can be told for paracompact spaces as was told for normal spaces on the colimits page, and all of this fits neatly within the general story that Misha (Gavrilovich) has been telling us, that many concepts in topology can be explicated in terms of lifting/extension properties. What the Michael selection theorem gives is a characterization of paracompact spaces in terms of an extension property (it is based ultimately on the characterization in terms of existence of partitions of unity), just as there is for normal spaces, and I think this type of characterization makes all those colimit results fairly easy to prove, in completely analogous fashion.

    Michael’s paper is from the mid-50’s and doesn’t use explicitly categorical language, but that language is really there and deserves to be brought out.

    Unfortunately I am busy with other things for most of the rest of this day…

    • CommentRowNumber8.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeMay 30th 2017

    Sounds great! There is no rush.

    • CommentRowNumber9.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeJun 3rd 2017

    Okay, I’ve finally written up something at colimits of paracompact spaces, mirroring colimits of normal spaces. I was delayed somewhat by being stuck for a while on an “it-is-easy-to-see” statement in Michael’s continuous selections paper, but anyway a pretty succinct proof of paracompactness for general CW-complexes is now there for your perusal.

    • CommentRowNumber10.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeJun 3rd 2017

    And to start bringing matters to more of a conclusion, I performed some more edits at CW-complexes are paracompact Hausdorff spaces.

    At some point I may write up some details of Michael’s selection criterion over at Michael’s theorems. Urs, I think you may have looked into this yourself already, right? You were looking for example at some of Akhil Mathew’s exposition(s). E. Michael as you know also proved that closed quotients of paracompact spaces are paracompact, which sounds sort of innocent at first blush, but it’s really not. I have not delved into this yet.

    • CommentRowNumber11.
    • CommentAuthorDavidRoberts
    • CommentTimeJun 3rd 2017
    • (edited Jun 3rd 2017)

    But a T 1T_1 paracompact space admits partitions of unity if and only if it is Hausdorff… (Wikipedia)

    • CommentRowNumber12.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeJun 3rd 2017

    Okay, thanks; I’ll look over this (and look over again at Michael’s paper, where I got the argument from). It’s not a seriously big deal for the current application, since it was already established that CW-complexes are T 4T_4.

    • CommentRowNumber13.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeJun 4th 2017
    • (edited Jun 4th 2017)

    David, I can’t tell which precise part of the Wikipedia page you are looking at. Meanwhile, I checked Michael again in two papers, and he says T 1T_1 in both of them.

    Actually checking up on all this would involve some serious chasing down rabbit holes, but it seems to me that a space with a cofinite topology might be a kind of acid test. (That’s compact and therefore paracompact, and also T 1T_1, right? But not Hausdorff.)

    • CommentRowNumber14.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeJun 4th 2017
    • (edited Jun 4th 2017)

    Well, from what I can tell according to this paper, theorem 4.6, page 7/12, “paracompact” for Michael must mean both paracompact and Hausdorff (perhaps in the same way that for some people, “compact” means “compact and Hausdorff”).

    Assuming this is the case: even better! In that case, Michael proves that if XX is T 1T_1, then paracompactness+Hausdorff is equivalent to his selection criterion. Now, one can prove by very soft means that CW-complexes are T 1T_1, meaning that the whole business with normality and Hausdorff can be dispensed with altogether, and Michael’s selection criterion then allows one to prove CW-complexes are paracompact and Hausdorff in very short order.

    • CommentRowNumber15.
    • CommentAuthorDavidRoberts
    • CommentTimeJun 4th 2017

    The relevant sentence is

    a T 1T_1 space is Hausdorff and paracompact if and only if it admits partitions of unity subordinate to any open cover

    But it doesn’t give a proof or reference.

    • CommentRowNumber16.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeJun 4th 2017
    • (edited Jun 4th 2017)

    But it doesn’t give a proof or reference.

    That’s okay. I think it must be right, because now I’ve found confirmation in Michael. In A Note on Paracompact Spaces, Michael defines “paracompact” on the first page to mean Hausdorff and every open cover has a locally finite open refinement, so that’s the definition he works with when he proves his theorem (which starts by recalling the equivalence with the subordinate partitions of unity property).

    • CommentRowNumber17.
    • CommentAuthorDavidRoberts
    • CommentTimeJun 4th 2017

    Glad it got sorted out :-)

    • CommentRowNumber18.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeJun 6th 2017

    Thank again, Todd! Very nice indeed.

    • CommentRowNumber19.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeJul 20th 2018

    Added that we are assuming points are closed as part of what we mean by “normal”.

    diff, v13, current

  1. Added a short exposition of the proof in Remark 3.2 using finite spaces and lifting properties.

    anonymous

    diff, v14, current

    • CommentRowNumber21.
    • CommentAuthorm
    • CommentTimeDec 5th 2018
    • (edited Dec 5th 2018)
    In fact, it does seem that in _colimits of paracompact Hausdorff spaces_, Theorem 3.1. (E. Michael’s selection theorem) and
    Lemma 3.2 imply that paracompactness of $T_1$ spaces are defined by a lifting property wrt maps $p$ occurring in relations $(R,p,q)$ as described in Theorem 3.1.


    The proof is a diagram chasing argument as follows. Assume a $T_1$ space is not paracompact and pick an $(R,p,q)$ provided by the theorem.
    Then the identity map $X\to X$ shows the lifting property $\emptyset\to X$ wrt $p$ fails.

    Assume $A$ is a paracompact $T_1$ space and $(R,p,q)$ is a selection wrt an $X$ and $B$ as described in the theorem.
    Let notation be as in Lemma 3.2. Given a map $f:A\to X$, by Theorem 3.1 the pullback $f^*R$ has a section, and therefore
    there is a lifting map wrt the original $p$.
  2. Re #20: that is quite amazing, thanks! At a quick glance, ZZ seems to be the pseudocircle? I don’t quite know what to make of that, but I find it fascinating!

    • CommentRowNumber23.
    • CommentAuthorGuest
    • CommentTimeDec 5th 2018
    Re #21: no, I dont think it is a pseudocircle, it is /\/\ rather than two points above the other two points.
    • CommentRowNumber24.
    • CommentAuthorGuest
    • CommentTimeDec 5th 2018
    >I don’t quite know what to make of that, but I find it fascinating!

    well, I suppose the main question is how much of topology can be done just in terms of diagram chasing, and lifting property in particular, and finite topological spaces. For example, ii shouldn't be too hard to write a parser for elementary diagram chasing properties wrt finite topological spaces and a proof system for implications between them, but I'm not sure it's been done.