Not signed in (Sign In)

Not signed in

Want to take part in these discussions? Sign in if you have an account, or apply for one below

  • Sign in using OpenID

Site Tag Cloud

2-category 2-category-theory abelian-categories adjoint algebra algebraic algebraic-geometry algebraic-topology analysis analytic-geometry arithmetic arithmetic-geometry book bundles calculus categorical categories category category-theory chern-weil-theory cohesion cohesive-homotopy-type-theory cohomology colimits combinatorics comma complex complex-geometry computable-mathematics computer-science constructive cosmology deformation-theory descent diagrams differential differential-cohomology differential-equations differential-geometry digraphs duality elliptic-cohomology enriched fibration finite foundation foundations functional-analysis functor gauge-theory gebra geometric-quantization geometry graph graphs gravity grothendieck group group-theory harmonic-analysis higher higher-algebra higher-category-theory higher-differential-geometry higher-geometry higher-lie-theory higher-topos-theory homological homological-algebra homotopy homotopy-theory homotopy-type-theory index-theory integration integration-theory k-theory lie-theory limits linear linear-algebra locale localization logic mathematics measure-theory modal modal-logic model model-category-theory monad monads monoidal monoidal-category-theory morphism motives motivic-cohomology nlab noncommutative noncommutative-geometry number-theory of operads operator operator-algebra order-theory pages pasting philosophy physics pro-object probability probability-theory quantization quantum quantum-field quantum-field-theory quantum-mechanics quantum-physics quantum-theory question representation representation-theory riemannian-geometry scheme schemes set set-theory sheaf simplicial space spin-geometry stable-homotopy-theory stack string string-theory superalgebra supergeometry svg symplectic-geometry synthetic-differential-geometry terminology theory topology topos topos-theory tqft type type-theory universal variational-calculus

Vanilla 1.1.10 is a product of Lussumo. More Information: Documentation, Community Support.

Welcome to nForum
If you want to take part in these discussions either sign in now (if you have an account), apply for one now (if you don't).
    • CommentRowNumber1.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeSep 11th 2010

    created coherence law

    (was surprised to find that we didn’t have this already. Or do we?)

    • CommentRowNumber2.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeSep 11th 2010

    a stub for associativity, supposed to be an entry that eventually serves to unify in a coherent way (hah!) the various sub-entries on the topic that we already have

    • CommentRowNumber3.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeSep 11th 2010

    We do have coherence theorem, and coherence theorem for monoidal categories. Another reasonable page to have (maybe a synonym for coherence law?) might be coherence condition.

    I think I would need a lot more convincing before accepting the thesis that all coherence laws ultimately boil down to contractibility conditions. There may be some kernel of truth to that, but the page comes off as a bit doctrinaire in my opinion (although I’d have to think hard before making concrete proposals for changes).

    • CommentRowNumber4.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeSep 11th 2010
    • (edited Sep 11th 2010)

    We do have coherence theorem,

    Right, so the way I put the links currently I am saying that a coherence theorem is the assertion that a given definition does satisfy the relevant coherence law .

    I find that more logical. Discussing a coherence theorem presupposes really that one has an idea of what a coherence law would be, so that one can then prove that it is satisfied.

    and coherence theorem for monoidal categories

    Ah, I wasn’t aware of that one. Have linked to it now from coherence law.

    Another reasonable page to have (maybe a synonym for coherence law?) might be coherence condition.

    Okay, I made that a redirect

    I think I would need a lot more convincing before accepting the thesis that all coherence laws ultimately boil down to contractibility conditions. There may be some kernel of truth to that, but the page comes off as a bit doctrinaire in my opinion (although I’d have to think hard before making concrete proposals for changes).

    Hm, okay. My impression was that this is the obvuious nice condition. Of course (see the discussion about cohomology that we are having here every second month) the term “coherence” is not copy-righted, so everybody is free to call things coherence laws that don’t fit this bill. But those of which we are confident that they are good do seem to fit this. Well, clearly saying “the space of choices is contractible” is not a precise formal statement. So that should be made more precise.

    What should we do? You want to put a caveat into the entry?

    • CommentRowNumber5.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeSep 11th 2010
    • (edited Sep 11th 2010)

    Todd, I just reminded myself of what you had written at coherence theorem for monoidal categories.

    There yourself you emphasize that MacLane’s coherence theorem asserts exactly that a certain groupoid – the one that is precisely the one that deserves to be called the “groupoid of possible choices of associators” – is contractible.

    To me that seems to be the statement that gets to the crux of the matter.

    • CommentRowNumber6.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeSep 11th 2010

    Yeah, I know Urs, but there are so many instances of coherence conditions out there that it would make me uncomfortable to baldly assert they all fit in this pattern. I think I said there’s a kernel of truth there, but I’d really have to think hard to be convinced that all cases boil down to this.

    • CommentRowNumber7.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeSep 11th 2010

    I left you a “query” box at coherence law. I strongly disagree with this formulation of coherence theorem.

    I am much more comfortable saying that a demand for contractibility conditions is often a useful heuristic for discovering coherence laws (and in hindsight might be used to justify the choice of coherence conditions in many classical structures, although I think this might depend on what has been proven or what one believes to be true about the periodic table).

    • CommentRowNumber8.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeSep 11th 2010

    but I’d really have to think hard to be convinced that all cases boil down to this.

    Okay, I currently have the opposite problem: I have to think hard to find a case that does not boil down to this!

    Help me, which case are you thinking of?

    • CommentRowNumber9.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeSep 11th 2010

    Oh, I see it in the query box now.

    • CommentRowNumber10.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeSep 11th 2010
    • (edited Sep 11th 2010)

    Hm , I am not sure if I get your point. Sorry, please bear with me. This is important.

    You are saying in that query box that braided monoidal categories are a counterexample to my claim, or at least make it questionable.

    So where do you see a non-contractible space of choices here?

    Let me ask: are you thinking of the fact that the double braiding

    B yxB xy:xyxy B_{y \otimes x}\circ B_{x \otimes y} : x \otimes y \to x \otimes y

    may not equal to the identity? In that case, just to clarify: this is not the space of choices that I mean. This is a π 3\pi_3 in a one-object-one-morphism 3-category. If I’d demand that to vanish I’d be demanding every nn-category to be the point!

    What I have in mind are the choices for the structure morphisms that relax the usual definition of a category: associativity and uniticity. It would seem to me that the two additional axioms in a braided monoidal category that demand the associator to be compatible with the braiding is exactly the condition that this space of ways of using associators to relax associativity in a one-object-one-morphisms 3-category is contractible.

    • CommentRowNumber11.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeSep 11th 2010

    Of course, the query box is specifically addressing the formulation of “coherence theorem”, not “coherence law”. Over time, the meaning of “coherence theorem” has transformed a bit, and the article coherence theorem gives some idea of the scope.

    I currently have the opposite problem: I have to think hard to find a case that does not boil down to this!

    That’s a fair question. Please take care to note that I am still open to being convinced myself, but I think the statements being put down at coherence law need a bit of qualification or warning or something.

    The thing is, you can have coherence conditions that come in from several directions but wind up interacting in complicated ways. A good idea might be symmetric monoidal closed categories. It’s sort of arguable that if you think of a symmetric monoidal category as a special type of 4-category, then the coherence laws for a symmetric monoidal category are ultimately derivable from contractibility conditions. And, there are coherence laws (usually called triangular equations) which govern adjunctions, so that the homs right adjoint to tensors are also governed by some sort of contractibility. But these coherence laws mix in very subtle ways, so that for example there are two definable maps of the form

    [[[x,I],I],I][[[x,I],I],I][[[x, I], I], I] \to [[[x, I], I], I]

    in an smc category, and no one in their right mind would demand them to be equal in the theory of smc cats. Same thing happens in *-autonomous categories, and really all over the place.

    • CommentRowNumber12.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeSep 11th 2010
    • (edited Sep 11th 2010)

    Okay, that helps. So I was thinking exclusively in terms of definitions of plain nn-categories, not nn-categories with extra operations on them.

    In that case, i think that contractibility is important, so I would like to see if we can agree in that case. Then I would tend to want to make in the entries a distinction between “coherence laws in the definition of plain n-categories” and “coherence laws for other kinds of algebraic structures”.

    • CommentRowNumber13.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeSep 11th 2010

    So what I am saying is that in cases where there is a mix of structures, so that the result is not just some case of (n,r)(n, r)-category, the precise selection of coherence laws (and particularly where to stop imposing more) is not a cut-and-dried matter to be decided by some omnibus statement about contractibility.

    If you are restricting the meaning of coherence law just to the case of (n,r)(n, r)-categories (where n=n = \infty is allowed), then I think I agree with you.

    • CommentRowNumber14.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeSep 11th 2010
    • (edited Sep 11th 2010)

    It’s sort of arguable that if you think of a symmetric monoidal category as a special type of 4-category, then the coherence laws for a symmetric monoidal category are ultimately derivable from contractibility conditions.

    Oh, really? That surprises me. (Of course I have no explicit control over either set of coherence laws in this case. )

    But let me ask directly: you are the one person on the planet who has written out coherence for 4-categories. You believe that this does not reproduce the coherence law for symmetric monoidal categories?

    Wouldn’t that be shocking? That would mean that if I start with your definition of tetracategory, I can find an another sensible definition of symmetric monoidal categories which is inequivalent to the standard one. No?

    • CommentRowNumber15.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeSep 11th 2010

    Sorry, I must have misrepresented myself when I said “it’s sort of arguable”. I didn’t mean it’s debatable, I meant one could argue that… (and IMO argue successfully). In other words, we are in agreement on that. Sorry for the confusion; it was my fault.

    • CommentRowNumber16.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeSep 11th 2010
    • (edited Sep 11th 2010)

    If you are restricting the meaning of coherence law just to the case of (n,r)(n, r)-categories (where n=n = \infty is allowed),

    Yes, that’s what i was thinking of exclusively. I think Mike also noticed this problem with me before. I tend to ignore categorical structures that are not special cases of (n,r)(n,r)-categories. ;)

    then I think I agree with you.

    All right, that’s a relief! No fun finding myself in such stark disagreement with Todd Trimle on technical matters!

    On the other hand, I was now already preparing my weapons and would next have started to prove to you that various n-categories obtained from accepted models of (,n)(\infty,n)-categories provably have the contractibility property. For instance the condition on a quasi-category CC is equivalent to demanding that the map [Δ[2],C][Λ 1[2],C][\Delta[2],C] \to [\Lambda^1[2],C] has as fibers contractible \infty-groupoids. That’s the coherence law for associativity in the corresponding algebraic A A_\infty-category.

    Okay, then I think I will now write the entries such as to make this distinction between the two kinds of coherence conditions clear. Then you can check if you like that better.

    • CommentRowNumber17.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeSep 11th 2010
    • (edited Sep 11th 2010)

    “It’s arguable” didn’t mean it’s debatable, I meant one could argue that

    Oop, sorry for misunderstanding that. Now that made me check my local disctionary. I had not, to be frank, been aware that this word can in fact be used in precisely two opposite senses.

    • CommentRowNumber18.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeSep 11th 2010
    • (edited Sep 11th 2010)

    Just for completeness, I should reply to this here, too:

    But these coherence laws mix in very subtle ways, so that for example there are two definable maps of the form

    [[[x,I],I],I][[[x,I],I],I][[[x, I], I], I] \to [[[x, I], I], I]

    in an smc category, and no one in their right mind would demand them to be equal in the theory of smc cats.

    Yes, and the reason one wouldn’t claim this is, analogous to the example one dim down with the double braiding, that this morphism witnesses a nontrivial π 4\pi_4 in a 4-category, and is not constructed exclusively from structure morphisms of the associator for 3-morphisms and its compatibilities with the 4-morphisms. Right?

    • CommentRowNumber19.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeSep 11th 2010

    @Urs #18: yes, I think you can put it that way.

    • CommentRowNumber20.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeSep 11th 2010
    • (edited Sep 11th 2010)

    It’s best to see this coming from geometric definitions of higher categories:

    say we start with an (2,1)(2,1)-category CC given as a simplicial set and want to build a bicategory out of it, with associators satisfying coherence.

    So we choose a composition operation by choosing 2-horn fillers. Then we choose associators by filling the spheres Δ[3]C\partial\Delta[3] \to C all whose faces are made from the chosen compositions. Now, of course in general CC will contain non-contractible such spheres. But by the defining properties of CC, those spheres whose four faces are compositions can be filled. So we do have associators. And then further, again by the definition properties all 3-spheres whose faces are the thus chosen associators can be filled. That’s what after we have made all our choices of composites and associators appears then to us as the coherence conditon that happens to be satisfied by these associators.

    So the thing is that of course CC is allowed to have non-contractible higher spheres. But we are guaranteed that whatever choices for composition, associators, pentagonators etc. we make, we will never wrap these cycles.

    By the way, I expanded associator.

    • CommentRowNumber21.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeSep 11th 2010

    Yes, I agree of course, except for “it’s best to see this coming from geometric definitions of higher categories”. The same philosophy holds in algebraic approaches. :-)

    • CommentRowNumber22.
    • CommentAuthorDavidRoberts
    • CommentTimeSep 13th 2010

    For instance the condition on a quasi-category CC is equivalent to demanding that the map [Δ[2],C][Λ 1[2],C][\Delta[2],C] \to [\Lambda^1[2],C] has as fibers contractible \infty-groupoids.

    In fact I would tend to say that it is not contractibility, but that certain maps are trivial fibrations, with contractible being replaced by blah*blah \to \ast a trivial fibration. cf the definition of a Segal category.

    • CommentRowNumber23.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeSep 13th 2010
    • (edited Sep 13th 2010)

    Yes, but that’s the same statement: the fibers of a trivial fibration are contractible, so that’s a parameterized collection of contractible spaces.

    Specifically, in our example the fact that [Δ[2],C][Λ 1[2],C][\Delta[2],C] \to [\Lambda^1[2],C] is a trivial fibration and hence has contractible fibers asserts all the components of the associativity coherence law between all tuples of objects.

    • CommentRowNumber24.
    • CommentAuthorDavidRoberts
    • CommentTimeSep 13th 2010

    the fibers of a trivial fibration are contractible

    no. They are weakly equivalent to the point, so that any two points in a fibre are connected by a path, any two such paths are homotopic (in the path) etc (sorry for teaching you to suck eggs). I don’t know if we actually need the space to _be_contractible, even though it often is.

    And saying something is a trivial fibration is neater than saying a bunch of fibres are contractible, which doesn’t tell us much about the map itself.

    • CommentRowNumber25.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeSep 13th 2010
    • (edited Sep 13th 2010)

    the fibers of a trivial fibration are contractible

    no. They are weakly equivalent to the point

    That’s the same!

    Maybe you have in mind a model of the situation where the oo-groupoids are modled by things that are not both fibrant and cofibrant. Then it’s different. But we don’t need to do that.

    • CommentRowNumber26.
    • CommentAuthorDavidRoberts
    • CommentTimeSep 13th 2010

    ah, ok then.

    • CommentRowNumber27.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeSep 13th 2010

    Right, so maybe my use of “space” interchangebly with “\infty-groupoid” was misleading. In as far as “space” here is read as “topological space” it is implicitly to be assumed to be a CW-complex (the realization of some Kan complex, specifically). So Whitehead’s theorem applies and tells us that every such that is weakly equivalent to the point has a contraction. And conversely of course.

    • CommentRowNumber28.
    • CommentAuthorDavidRoberts
    • CommentTimeSep 13th 2010

    Yes - I was thinking while offline that Trimble fundamental n-groupoids genuinely have a space of choices, which is not necessarily ’nice’. Even though such choices are given, this is pretty much an arbitrary choice. One could consider a geometrisation of his algebraic definition, much as we now have an algebraisation of the geometric definition of an n-groupoid as a certain Kan complex, and then I would prefer to rely on a formulation saying ’such and such is an acyclic fibration’. I would like to see (and yes, the onus is on me to put it in) reference to complete segal spaces or the like in discussion of coherence conditions like this.

    • CommentRowNumber29.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeSep 13th 2010

    Not quite following what is trying to be said in #28.

    • 0-cells in Π n(X)\Pi_n(X) are points of XX.

    • 1-cells are paths IXI \to X.

    • (n1)(n-1)-cells are maps D n1XD^{n-1} \to X.

    • nn-cells are homotopy-rel-boundary classes of maps D nXD^n \to X.

    There is a canonical set of operations on these cells which specifies the structure of Π n(X)\Pi_n(X), defined by pure abstract nonsense. So where are the ’arbitrary’ choices in this specification?

    • CommentRowNumber30.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeSep 13th 2010

    I’d think the coherence law in the definition of Trimble n-category is exhibited by the fact that the topological spaces Hom(I,I n)Hom(I, I^{\vee n}) are contractible. These are the “spaces of choices”.

    • CommentRowNumber31.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeSep 13th 2010

    Yes. Could someone explain how these choices are ’arbitrary’, or what that means precisely?

    • CommentRowNumber32.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeSep 13th 2010

    Might “arbitrariness”, where it enters in making geometric notions of higher category algebraic, be closely related to “bias”, in the sense of choosing some operations over other available ones as primitives in the theory? (I think of Trimble n-cats as an “unbiased” notion.)

    • CommentRowNumber33.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeSep 13th 2010

    Since it is a very good example, I think, I added the case of Trimble nn-categories as one brief paragraph to the Examples-section at coherence law.

    • CommentRowNumber34.
    • CommentAuthorDavidRoberts
    • CommentTimeSep 14th 2010

    the fact that the topological spaces Hom(I,I n)Hom(I, I^{\vee n}) are contractible

    this did occur to me, and I realised that it negated my argument - I was thinking of iterated path spaces of the given space XX, which obviously can be a bit nasty for general XX (but then the fundamental nn-groupoid might not be the right construction, and some sort of profinite/prodiscrete/shape thing might be better). As far as arbitrary choices go, I may not be recalling the definition of Trimble category correctly, but Todd is correct in his appraisal of my #28 - there is a canonical set of operations, but these aren’t the only ones, if one is choosing between biased and unbiased. In my thesis when I was dealing with the definition of Π 2(X)\Pi_2(X) for XX a topological groupoid, one had to be very explicit and careful as to the choices of the structure maps, which essentially came from choosing elements of the various hom-spaces C(I n,I m)C(I^n,I^m). In my setting I couldn’t use the canonical choices, and had to use a mix of biased, unbiased and non-standard, piecewise affine transformations. In fact my space of available choices was only a subspace of C(I n,I m)C(I^n,I^m), and not one that was obviously contractible, although I’m guess it is, probably some sort of deformation retract of the full hom-space.

    • CommentRowNumber35.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeSep 14th 2010
    • (edited Sep 14th 2010)

    Hi David,

    you know this, but just for amplification and for the record: the point of these operadic definitions of higher categories is that no specific choices for composites are enforced, but that instead all possible ways to compose are kept tract of while keeping them under algebraic control.

    So to some extent these definitions might actually be re4garded as sitting half-way in between the purely geometric ones where just the existence of a space of composites is assserted and the bi-tri-tetracategory ones, where a speicifc composite is chosen.

    Here for Trimble n-category there are just the full spaces of composites without a choice of composite as in the geometric apporach, but then on top of this is an algebraic structure that governs how these spaces of choices connect together.

    • CommentRowNumber36.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeSep 15th 2010

    added to the Examples-section at coherence law a discussion of coherence in nn-groupoids modeled as Kan complexes