Want to take part in these discussions? Sign in if you have an account, or apply for one below
Vanilla 1.1.10 is a product of Lussumo. More Information: Documentation, Community Support.
Hi all, I’m meeting a weird universal property in CAT, and started wondering whether the enriched toolbox would apply.
I have functors
, , , , and ,
plus natural transformations and .
I have been considering the following two universal properties.
The pullback in the (op?)lax slice CAT / sets (I hope you can guess what I mean by lax slice).
Same as (1), but imposing furthermore that the domain be 1, i.e., that the universal object is a set.
I think there are various ways to calculate these, the most obvious, for (2), being to calculate the limits of all functors to reflect the whole diagram in sets (actually [1,sets]), and then compute the limit there. Another being to calculate (1), and then take the limit (more precisely the right extension along the unique functor to 1).
I’m interested in whether these universal properties are definable by weighted colimits in CAT, or as limits in sets seen as a complete object of the 2-category CAT with its standard Yoneda structure. Notably, are there results explaining why the various ways of computing these limits coincide?
The pullback of what two morphisms in ? I see a span in ,not a cospan; was that a typo?
You mean, what you want is a pushout in the lax slice 2-category? I also don’t quite understand what you mean by “imposing that the domain be 1”. Maybe you could give an example?
Sorry, I don’t seem to explain myself well.
Yes, what I want is a pushout in the lax slice 2-category (although I’m not sure the ’2’ matters here).
By “imposing that the domain be 1”, I mean the same as when computing a Kan extension along the unique 1-cell to 1. That gives perhaps the best possible example: are, e.g., right extensions of a 1-cell, say , along another particular examples of limits in the ambient 2-category (as opposed to in )?
The original example was similar, but with interchange of limits: given functors , , and such that , one would compute limF, limG, and the induced map , and then pull limH back along some element to obtain a set . This element induces a transformation , and I think may be obtained alternatively by first computing the pushout of and in the lax slice , and then taking the limit of the resulting functor.
Is this clearer?
By “imposing that the domain be 1”, I mean the same as when computing a Kan extension along the unique 1-cell to 1.
What I was looking for was a precise statement of the universal property you are after. Your mention of Kan extensions gives me some vague idea of what you might mean, but not a precise one.
Using the notations of the first post, the second universal property is that of a terminal object in the category with objects tuples of a set , and natural transformations and such that , and morphisms all transformations such that and .
Okay. I’m sorry for being a bit snappy, and for taking so long to reply now; I had something else on my mind. But it’s good, because if I had tried to answer you a week ago, I don’t think I would have had the right answer, whereas now I think I see it.
Suppose we have a 2-category equipped with proarrows . (I know this may seem like a great leap into abstraction, but trust me.) Suppose is a proarrow, and is an arrow. Then a limit of weighted by is an arrow equipped with an isomorphism . Here denotes the right adjoint on one side to composition of proarrows, and denotes the proarrow represented by (its right adjoint is ).
In particular, if with profunctors as proarrows, then:
Given , take for the unique arrow. Then -weighted limits are ordinary limits of -shaped diagrams.
Given , take ; then -weighted limits are ordinary (pointwise) right Kan extensions along .
Moreover, phrasing things this way, we have a nice functoriality property: given and , we have
Now, if is equipped with proarrows and the bicategory of proarrows has local colimits (colimits in hom-categories preserved by composition), then we can construct a new 2-category equipped with proarrows, denoted , as follows.
Its objects are categories enriched in the bicategory of proarrows for . These are like “monads with many objects”. They have a collection of objects , each assigned to an object of as its “extent”, and if and have extents and , then the hom-object is a proarrow . There are then composition/multiplication and unit morphisms as usual.
An arrow from to consists of an assignation of an object of to every object of , together with an arrow (not a proarrow) in , and for each in morphisms .
A proarrow in is a “bimodule” in the obvious sense, and the 2-cells are bimodule morphisms.
If has one object, one arrow, and its proarrows are a monoidal category , then is the bicategory of -enriched categories, functors, and profunctors.
Note also that every object of induces an object of , call it , which has one object of extent and the unit profunctor as . This is a full embedding .
Now, let’s take with profunctors as the proarrows, and suppose given the data described in your first post. Then there is an object of , let’s call it , described as follows. It has three objects , , and , with , , and . We have , , and all other hom-objects empty.
Now your functors and transformations describe an arrow in . I claim that the object you want is the right Kan extension of along the unique arrow in . Moreover, the fact that your two ways of computing this agree boils down to the functoriality of limits I described above.
On the one hand, we have an object with three objects all of extent and only trivial homs. An arrow is exactly a cospan in , and its Kan extension along in is the pullback of this cospan. The process of “reflecting the whole diagram in ” I believe corresponds to taking the Kan extension along the evident arrow ; thus the composite Kan extension is just the Kan extension along .
On the other hand, we also have a category which is the collage of . This means it is the lax colimit of regarded as a lax functor into , and it has the additional universal property that the coprojections into the colimit are representable profunctors, and detect representability in the sense that a profunctor out of is representable iff its composites with all the coprojections are so. Moreover, the coprojections fit together to give an arrow in such that is a (“Morita”) equivalence.
Now the arrow determined by can equivalently be regarded as a lax cocone under qua lax functor into , with vertex . Since colimits in (lax) slice categories are just (lax) colimits of the underlying objects, the pushout of this diagram in is just , and the induced functor is the same as that induced by and the Morita equivalence — which is also the right Kan extension of along .
Therefore, the process of taking the pushout in and then taking the limit of the resulting -diagram is equivalent to first Kan extending along , then along ; thus the composite is again the Kan extension along .
The nLab doesn’t yet do a great job of explaining the construction and collages, I think. Good papers to read are “Enriched categories and cohomology” and “Cauchy characterization of enriched categories” by Ross Street, and “An axiomatics for bicategories of modules” by Carboni, Kasangian, and Walters.
No, they don’t; those papers are written entirely in terms of bicategories, with functors considered as the profunctors with right adjoints. This simplifies things somewhat (at the price of making it impossible to distinguish between a category and its Cauchy completion).
Dear Mike,
Thanks, I’m almost there! However, I’m clearly not yet autonomous in the use of these tools, and you’re probably not ok for being systematically used as a reference manual. So is there some place I could look up for known facts on these things?
E.g., I’d expect the following to hold:
has all right extensions (but how are they computed?),
so, starting from the original , and , ,
It may be faster for me to answer your questions directly than to try to track down references; there isn’t a good textbook or anything on profunctor theory (sadly). For any bicategory with sufficient limits in its hom-categories, the bicategory has right extensions and right liftings, computed in basically the same way as right extensions and liftings are in using the right extensions in and an end-like limit. But perhaps what you wanted to ask about was right extensions of functors, which is the sense in which we “extend along ”. Those are a limit-notion and depend on completeness properties of the target object — in your case, . I don’t know offhand a general result about how completeness properties of an object of a bicategory/equipment extend to its image in , but it should be provable.
1 to 12 of 12