Not signed in (Sign In)

Not signed in

Want to take part in these discussions? Sign in if you have an account, or apply for one below

  • Sign in using OpenID

Site Tag Cloud

2-category 2-category-theory abelian-categories adjoint algebra algebraic algebraic-geometry algebraic-topology analysis analytic-geometry arithmetic arithmetic-geometry book bundles calculus categorical categories category category-theory chern-weil-theory cohesion cohesive-homotopy-type-theory cohomology colimits combinatorics complex complex-geometry computable-mathematics computer-science constructive cosmology deformation-theory descent diagrams differential differential-cohomology differential-equations differential-geometry digraphs duality elliptic-cohomology enriched fibration foundation foundations functional-analysis functor gauge-theory gebra geometric-quantization geometry graph graphs gravity grothendieck group group-theory harmonic-analysis higher higher-algebra higher-category-theory higher-differential-geometry higher-geometry higher-lie-theory higher-topos-theory homological homological-algebra homotopy homotopy-theory homotopy-type-theory index-theory integration integration-theory k-theory lie-theory limits linear linear-algebra locale localization logic mathematics measure-theory modal modal-logic model model-category-theory monad monads monoidal monoidal-category-theory morphism motives motivic-cohomology nforum nlab noncommutative noncommutative-geometry number-theory of operads operator operator-algebra order-theory pages pasting philosophy physics pro-object probability probability-theory quantization quantum quantum-field quantum-field-theory quantum-mechanics quantum-physics quantum-theory question representation representation-theory riemannian-geometry scheme schemes set set-theory sheaf sheaves simplicial space spin-geometry stable-homotopy-theory stack string string-theory superalgebra supergeometry svg symplectic-geometry synthetic-differential-geometry terminology theory topology topos topos-theory tqft type type-theory universal variational-calculus

Vanilla 1.1.10 is a product of Lussumo. More Information: Documentation, Community Support.

Welcome to nForum
If you want to take part in these discussions either sign in now (if you have an account), apply for one now (if you don't).
    • CommentRowNumber1.
    • CommentAuthorAndrew Stacey
    • CommentTimeApr 29th 2013

    Listening to a talk recently on trace-class operators on locally convex topological vector spaces (so, not assumed to be Hilbert spaces - though Banach would do for what I’m going to describe), I ended up wondering whether or not the following was an example of a standard categorical construction.

    The idea is to have something like a category except that there are two types of morphism between the objects. Naïvely, the definition might go like this:

    1. A class of objects, say OO
    2. For each pair of objects, say a,bOa,b \in O, two sets M(a,b)M(a,b) and N(a,b)N(a,b)

    such that:

    1. The data (O,M(,))(O,M(-,-)) forms a category,
    2. The data (O,N(,))(O,N(-,-)) satisfies the composition law but need not have identities,
    3. (O,M(,))(O,M(-,-)) acts on (O,N(,))(O,N(-,-)) in that there is a product M(a,b)×N(b,c)N(a,c)M(a,b) \times N(b,c) \to N(a,c) satisfying all the obvious coherences.

    The motivating example being where the objects are locally convex topological vector spaces, M(a,b)M(a,b) are continuous linear maps, and N(a,b)N(a,b) are trace-class maps. Note that the identity is rarely trace-class so that excludes (O,N(,))(O,N(-,-)) from being a category, and that the natural map from trace-class to all is not necessarily injective so this isn’t a category with distinguished morphisms.

    One could also formulate cobordisms in this way, with diffeomorphisms as the M(,)M(-,-) morphisms, since one has to do a bit of fiddling to make the identity map a cobordism.

    • CommentRowNumber2.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeApr 29th 2013

    An ideal in the monoid-oid of morphisms, hence a sieve. Isn’t that what you describe?

    • CommentRowNumber3.
    • CommentAuthorAndrew Stacey
    • CommentTimeApr 29th 2013

    Close, but fails on two counts which are exhibited by the motivating example of trace-class operators:

    1. Trace-class operators are not always a subset of all operators, so the “category” (O,N(,))(O,N(-,-)) is not a subcategory of (O,M(,))(O,M(-,-)).
    2. The identity is rarely a trace-class operators, so the “category” (O,N(,))(O,N(-,-)) lacks identities.
    • CommentRowNumber4.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeApr 29th 2013
    • (edited Apr 29th 2013)

    Re 1: You consider trace-class operators which are not linear and/or not continuous?

    Re 2: if NN is or were a sieve inside MM, then it need not have identities.

    • CommentRowNumber5.
    • CommentAuthorAndrew Stacey
    • CommentTimeApr 29th 2013

    Re 1: I should be more explicit in what I mean by “trace-class operator”. I mean an element in the trace-closure of the tensor product of aba' \otimes b. I guess I was a bit lax here, sorry.

    Re 2: Okay, that’s not what the page sieve says:

    A sieve in a category C is a full subcategory closed under precomposition with morphisms in C.

    The “full subcategory” seems pretty clear to me that it contains identities.

    • CommentRowNumber6.
    • CommentAuthorzskoda
    • CommentTimeApr 29th 2013
    • (edited Apr 29th 2013)

    5 – about sieve – this definition is strange…ideal in a monoid, an Ω\Omega-group, and in particular in a unital ring is not having a multiplicative identity (otherwise it is the whole ring), hence it is not a unital subring. Probably, the page sieve has it wrong…

    • CommentRowNumber7.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeApr 29th 2013
    • (edited Apr 29th 2013)

    @Andrew, Zoran: Go one line further in sieve.

    (I guess that Idea-section could do with a better lead-in, but I won’t look into that right now.)

    • CommentRowNumber8.
    • CommentAuthorzskoda
    • CommentTimeApr 29th 2013
    • (edited Apr 29th 2013)

    So, is the sieve in the sense of that definition the same as an ideal in a category or not ? (I understand that the slice category version works well fitting with the terminology for Grothendieck topologies, besides I read that exposition in Lurie some time ago). I am having in mind predominantly the context of enriched categories where the case of an enriched category with one object should be a special case, hence a ring as an one object version of an additive category.

    • CommentRowNumber9.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeApr 29th 2013

    A sieve over an object is a right ideal: a collection of maps into that object which is closed under precompposition.

    • CommentRowNumber10.
    • CommentAuthorzskoda
    • CommentTimeApr 29th 2013

    I understand the “right” modifier, but still, for additive category with one object I do not see how do you exclude the identity (if you include it, you get everything, hence one has only one such right ideal for one object additive category…).

    • CommentRowNumber11.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeApr 29th 2013

    It almost seems as if we are discussing what an ideal is and what a sieve is. Is that right? :-)

    Zoran, are you asking the following:

    given a ring RR and an ideal NRN \hookrightarrow R, why does that define a sieve over the unique object of BR\mathbf{B}R?

    • CommentRowNumber12.
    • CommentAuthorzskoda
    • CommentTimeApr 29th 2013
    • (edited Apr 29th 2013)

    I am asking how come given the proper ideal NRN\hookrightarrow R, which clearly does not have an identity element from RR, what then with the identity morphism for the unique object in BR\mathbf{B}R, which should be in the corresponding sieve (the same elements as morphisms of right multiplication), if sieve is a subcategory, as the entry says? What am I misreading ?

    • CommentRowNumber13.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeApr 29th 2013

    Zoran,

    please read beyond the first line of the entry. It says (and I have now amplified this more in the new version) that a sieve on an object is a full subcategory closed under precomposition in the slice over it.

    • CommentRowNumber14.
    • CommentAuthorzskoda
    • CommentTimeApr 29th 2013
    • (edited Apr 29th 2013)

    I see now – my confusion, prompted by 2 was that “ideal” suggestion and in categories I think of ideals quite differently (as a congruence on a category, not in any of the senses covered in nnLab, it seems), than of the sieves (strangely, the entry ideal has nothing for the case of additive categories).

    • CommentRowNumber15.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeApr 29th 2013

    Toby has written these entries in quite some generality. The entry closer to the standard notion is ideal in a monoid.

    • CommentRowNumber16.
    • CommentAuthorzskoda
    • CommentTimeApr 29th 2013

    in quite some generality

    I meant the obvious: for categories as oidification of monoids.

    • CommentRowNumber17.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeApr 29th 2013

    @Zoran, not sure what you mean that you meant. Sorry. Can you just say again which of the various statements that we talked about you are making which statement about? Sorry.

    @Andrew: to answer your question in the case that NN is not a subcategory of MM: then what you have is still an action of a category of MM an NN.

    • CommentRowNumber18.
    • CommentAuthorKarol Szumiło
    • CommentTimeApr 30th 2013

    Those look like categories enriched over a particular monoidal category, namely, the category of pairs of sets (M,N)(M, N) with the product (M 0,N 0)(M 1,N 1)=(M 0×M 1,M 0×N 1)(M_0, N_0) \otimes (M_1, N_1) = (M_0 \times M_1, M_0 \times N_1) and the unit (*,)(*, \varnothing). This is an instance of a Day convolution product, but only over a promonoidal category, not an honest monoidal category. Moreover, this monoidal category is not symmetric and the theory of enriched categories over it may be a little hairy so I’m not sure how useful this observation is.

    • CommentRowNumber19.
    • CommentAuthorTobyBartels
    • CommentTimeApr 30th 2013

    Since NMN \nsubseteq M, we have more of a module than an ideal?

    • CommentRowNumber20.
    • CommentAuthorAndrew Stacey
    • CommentTimeApr 30th 2013

    Karol, Thanks! That’s not quite it, but it’s given me the clue as to what it is. I had an inkling that there would be some sort of enriched description of this but (as I’m no category theorist) had no idea how to formulate it. I’ve been wanting to say “enriched over “Groups ×\times GG-sets” except that that only describes the automorphisms and not the morphisms and I didn’t know how to unroll that to a proper description. Seeing what you wrote showed me how to do that.

    The category that it is enriched over is the category of pairs of sets, but the product is actually:

    (M 0,N 0)(M 1,N 1)=(M 0×M 1,M 0×N 1⨿N 0×N 1⨿N 0×M 1) (M_0,N_0) \otimes (M_1, N_1) = (M_0 \times M_1, M_0 \times N_1 \amalg N_0 \times N_1 \amalg N_0 \times M_1)

    I guess one could simply make this an ordinary category by folding the pairs into a coproduct, but I’d hope that there was some gain to regarding it in this enriched way.

    This product Is symmetric so that should make life easier - or does your dire warning still hold?

    • CommentRowNumber21.
    • CommentAuthorKarol Szumiło
    • CommentTimeApr 30th 2013

    You are right, I’ve failed to take into account that N-morphisms also have composition. And from your third summand I gather that you want M-morphisms to act on N-morphisms from both sides. This indeed makes the monoidal structure symmetric. In fact, now it has a very nice description. Let E={1,e}E = \{ 1, e \} be a monoid with 11 a unit and ee an idempotent. Consider it as a monoidal category with elements of EE as objects, no non-trivial morphisms and the monoidal product induced by the multiplication of EE. Then your monoidal product is the Day convolution of functors ESetE \to \mathrm{Set}. Since EE is commutative this makes Set E\mathrm{Set}^E into a closed symmetric monoidal category. It is also complete and cocomplete (even locally presentable) so all the standard theory of enriched categories is available.

    I think it is more natural (and more categorical) to think of objects in this category as pairs of sets. (Just as it is more natural to think of graded modules and rings as sequences of abelian groups as opposed to abelian groups equipped with a decomposition into a direct sum of a sequence of subgroups.)

    • CommentRowNumber22.
    • CommentAuthorAndrew Stacey
    • CommentTimeApr 30th 2013
    • (edited Apr 30th 2013)

    Fantastic! Thanks again. Just one query:

    I think it is more natural (and more categorical) to think of objects in this category as pairs of sets.

    What do you mean by “this category” here? Do you mean the base category that we’re enriching over? If so, I agree. But you could mean the enriched category, in which case I’m confused.

    So we can view a cobordism category as one of these, with diffeomorphisms and cobordisms as the two pieces of the morphisms, and we can view LCTVS as one of these, with a (functorial) choice of topology on the tensor product. Then a field theory is an enriched functor from one to the other.

    LCTVS also has some extra structure in that there’s a natural transformation from the module part to the main part. Ack, let’s have some terminology! Given a category enriched over Set E\Set^E let’s write M 1(a,b)M_1(a,b) and M e(a,b)M_e(a,b) for the two pieces of the morphisms. So in LCTVS, we have a natural transformation M e(,)M 1(,)M_e(-,-) \to M_1(-,-). Moreover, LCTVS is actually enriched over LCTVS E\LCTVS^E if we choose some functorial LCTVS structure on the morphism sets.

    Hmm, this might be a fun project to use to learn about enriched categories. Anyone feel this is doomed to failure?

    • CommentRowNumber23.
    • CommentAuthorKarol Szumiło
    • CommentTimeApr 30th 2013

    What do you mean by “this category” here? Do you mean the base category that we’re enriching over? If so, I agree.

    Yes, that’s what I mean.

    So in LCTVS, we have a natural transformation M e(,)M 1(,)M_e(-,-) \to M_1(-,-).

    You can extend EE to a symmetric monoidal category EE' by adding an extra arrow e1e \to 1. Enrichment over Set E\Set^{E'} should capture this extra structure.

    • CommentRowNumber24.
    • CommentAuthorAndrew Stacey
    • CommentTimeApr 30th 2013

    Right, but then I lose the example of cobordisms.

    I think that LCTVS is an example of a very highly structured category (Todd Trimble and I had a long discussion about the variety of monoidal structures on it somewhere in the nCafé) so basing everything on that example might end up with something so structured that there aren’t any other examples of it.

    On the other hand, I guess that the functor EEE \to E' makes any Set E\Set^{E'}-category automatically a Set E\Set^E-category and using the Set E\Set^{E'}-structure means that any properties that come from it being an enriched category (as you hint at in #21) can be assumed to respect this natural transformation.

    Another example would be Euclidean spaces with isometries and linear maps. That is, isometries form the 11-morphisms and linear maps form the ee-morphisms. (This is over Set E\Set^E, of course, not Set E\Set^{E'}.)

    • CommentRowNumber25.
    • CommentAuthorTobias Fritz
    • CommentTimeMay 1st 2013
    • (edited May 1st 2013)
    Without having looked at any of this in detail, I wonder whether the following paper might be relevant:

    Nuclear and Trace Ideals in Tensored *-Categories
    • CommentRowNumber26.
    • CommentAuthoradeelkh
    • CommentTimeMay 1st 2013

    (Just as it is more natural to think of graded modules and rings as sequences of abelian groups as opposed to abelian groups equipped with a decomposition into a direct sum of a sequence of subgroups.)

    Sorry to get off-topic, but would you mind explaining briefly why that is? I've heard someone say this before but I wasn't convinced by their argument.

    • CommentRowNumber27.
    • CommentAuthorAndrew Stacey
    • CommentTimeMay 1st 2013

    Tobias, That is indeed a very interesting paper. I read through parts of it (skipping the probabilistic bits) and there are some close connections. The main difference is that I don’t want to assume that my “other morphisms” are a subset of the “true morphisms”. In Hilbert spaces then this is true, but other examples fail for that.

    (I also strongly disagree with their definition of a “nuclear” object. In LCTVS then nuclear spaces do not have the property that they require. I’m pretty sure that only finite dimensional LCTVS would satisfy their definition of being a nuclear object.)

    • CommentRowNumber28.
    • CommentAuthorKarol Szumiło
    • CommentTimeMay 1st 2013

    Sorry to get off-topic, but would you mind explaining briefly why that is? I’ve heard someone say this before but I wasn’t convinced by their argument.

    I’d say that this is largely a matter of aesthetics. If you like to think abstractly, then defining graded rings as sequences makes it easier to put them into a categorical context.

    But more importantly, if you have a graded ring (say concentrated in nonnegative degrees) defined as a sequence of abelian groups, then there is more than one way to turn it into an actual ring. The obvious thing is to take the direct sum, but you could also take the product. In fact if your ring is the cohomology ring of a space (note that the cohomology ring is first given as a sequence of cohomology groups), then you want to take the product more often than not. This is a very useful point of view for complex oriented cohomology theories. They come equipped with formal group laws which can be used to describe a lot of cohomological structure but in order to exploit them we should use products rather than direct sums (e.g. we think of cohomology of P \mathbb{C} P^\infty as a power series ring rather than a polynomial ring.) This point would be very opaque if we insisted on the “direct sum definition” of graded rings.

    • CommentRowNumber29.
    • CommentAuthoradeelkh
    • CommentTimeMay 1st 2013

    Karol, thanks for the explanation.

    • CommentRowNumber30.
    • CommentAuthorMike Shulman
    • CommentTimeMay 2nd 2013

    Adeel, my impression has been that one is not necessarily “more natural” than the other in the abstract, but that it depends on what you are doing with your graded modules. In algebraic topology and category theory, it’s more natural to regard them as sequences. But I’ve been told that in some places at least in algebraic geometry, the other perspective is more natural.

    • CommentRowNumber31.
    • CommentAuthoradeelkh
    • CommentTimeMay 3rd 2013

    That makes sense. I can confirm that algebraic geometers use the decomposition definition, probably universally.