Not signed in (Sign In)

Not signed in

Want to take part in these discussions? Sign in if you have an account, or apply for one below

  • Sign in using OpenID

Site Tag Cloud

2-category 2-category-theory abelian-categories adjoint algebra algebraic algebraic-geometry algebraic-topology analysis analytic-geometry arithmetic arithmetic-geometry book bundles calculus categorical categories category category-theory chern-weil-theory cohesion cohesive-homotopy-type-theory cohomology colimits combinatorics complex complex-geometry computable-mathematics computer-science constructive cosmology deformation-theory descent diagrams differential differential-cohomology differential-equations differential-geometry digraphs duality elliptic-cohomology enriched fibration foundation foundations functional-analysis functor gauge-theory gebra geometric-quantization geometry graph graphs gravity grothendieck group group-theory harmonic-analysis higher higher-algebra higher-category-theory higher-differential-geometry higher-geometry higher-lie-theory higher-topos-theory homological homological-algebra homotopy homotopy-theory homotopy-type-theory index-theory integration integration-theory internal-categories k-theory lie-theory limits linear linear-algebra locale localization logic mathematics measure measure-theory modal modal-logic model model-category-theory monad monads monoidal monoidal-category-theory morphism motives motivic-cohomology nlab noncommutative noncommutative-geometry number-theory of operads operator operator-algebra order-theory pages pasting philosophy physics pro-object probability probability-theory quantization quantum quantum-field quantum-field-theory quantum-mechanics quantum-physics quantum-theory question representation representation-theory riemannian-geometry scheme schemes set set-theory sheaf simplicial space spin-geometry stable-homotopy-theory stack string string-theory superalgebra supergeometry svg symplectic-geometry synthetic-differential-geometry terminology theory topology topos topos-theory tqft type type-theory universal variational-calculus

Vanilla 1.1.10 is a product of Lussumo. More Information: Documentation, Community Support.

Welcome to nForum
If you want to take part in these discussions either sign in now (if you have an account), apply for one now (if you don't).
    • CommentRowNumber1.
    • CommentAuthorMike Shulman
    • CommentTimeJan 2nd 2010

    Wrote generic proof with some comments about a couple seemingly weaker versions of the axiom of choice that I've never seen mentioned anywhere before (has anyone else?). Toby and I noticed these a little bit ago while thinking about exact completions, but I just now realized that they're actually good for something: proving that the category of anafunctors between two small categories is essentially small (in the "projective" way).

    • CommentRowNumber2.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeFeb 21st 2013

    I wrote in some material at generic proof which replaces one of the “seemingly”s with something more definitive (that the assumption “Set ex/lexSet_{ex/lex} is wellpowered” is weaker than “Set ex/lexSet_{ex/lex} is a topos”).

    • CommentRowNumber3.
    • CommentAuthorTobyBartels
    • CommentTimeFeb 21st 2013
    • (edited Feb 21st 2013)

    I added a diagram to generic proof, and explanations of what ν *θ\nu^*\theta and Set Set^\to mean (I assume).

    • CommentRowNumber4.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeFeb 21st 2013

    trivial edit:

    I changed an

     \rlap
    

    to

     \mathrlap
    

    The former has no effect. The latter does what you think it should do.

    • CommentRowNumber5.
    • CommentAuthorZhen Lin
    • CommentTimeFeb 21st 2013

    Is there a motivation behind the name? What is it a generic proof of?

    • CommentRowNumber6.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeFeb 21st 2013
    • (edited Feb 21st 2013)

    I was about to suggest that a comment on that needs to be added.

    I suppose this is referring to Proof as in type theory being just a “term of a type”, hence a map into some object. So a “generic proof” is like a universal bundle: any one on any given object is obtained from the generic/universal one by pulling it back along some classifying map.

    I won’t add anything to the entry, since I don’t know the background. But it would be good if somebody else did.

    • CommentRowNumber7.
    • CommentAuthorZhen Lin
    • CommentTimeFeb 21st 2013

    Yes, that makes sense. I suppose its universal property is best understood in terms of some kind of fibred preorder reflection of the canonical codomain fibration of the category.

    • CommentRowNumber8.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeFeb 21st 2013

    Undoubtedly related, the notion of tripos involves a notion of generic predicate, again involving a weak universal property that relates a base category of terms CC to a hyperdoctrine of predicates over CC. It is especially easy to describe if CC is cartesian closed: if Pred:C opHeytAlgPred: C^{op} \to HeytAlg is the hyperdoctrine and |Pred|:C opSet{|Pred|}: C^{op} \to Set its composition with the forgetful functor to SetSet, then a generic predicate is tantamount to weak representability of |Pred|{|Pred|}, i.e., an object PP together with a given epimorphism C(,P)|Pred|C(-, P) \to {|Pred|}. The image of the identity 1 P1_P as an element of |Pred|(P){|Pred|}(P) is the generic predicate in question.

    I don’t have a very full understanding of this, but there are two paths to get from a partial combinatory algebra AA to a realizability topos. One is through triposes and generic predicates and involves a kind of allegorical way of passing to an exact completion:

    • First pass from a unitary pretabular allegory given by a tripos associated with AA, to a unitary tabular allegory, by splitting coreflexives. This is analogous to a regular completion.

    • Then split equivalence relations in the unitary tabular allegory. This is analogous to taking an ex/reg completion.

    (The two steps can be combined into one by splitting PERs. But I find it more understandable to think of it in two steps.)

    The other path is through partitioned assemblies associated with AA. This is a category with weak dependent products and a generic proof. By Menni’s thesis, the exact completion of this category is a topos.

    I would really like to have a unified understanding of these two paths, and have this reflected in the nLab.

    • CommentRowNumber9.
    • CommentAuthorMike Shulman
    • CommentTimeFeb 21st 2013

    I don’t quite understand the origin of the name “generic proof” either, except for the same vague intuition as in Urs’s #6.

    • CommentRowNumber10.
    • CommentAuthorTobyBartels
    • CommentTimeFeb 22nd 2013

    Even if we don't know the truth, we could add the vague intuition of Urs #6 as a conjecture. It would make the whole thing seems less of a non sequitur.

    • CommentRowNumber11.
    • CommentAuthorFinnLawler
    • CommentTimeFeb 22nd 2013

    I don’t mean to highjack the thread, but I’d like to reply to what Todd wrote about the two kinds of realizability constructions:

    I would really like to have a unified understanding of these two paths, and have this reflected in the nLab.

    So would I, and I’m writing my thesis on one aspect of that understanding, namely that you can organise predicates into either fibrations (like the effective tripos) or bicategories of relations (like Rel of the category of assemblies), and that with enough structure the 2-categories of these are equivalent. There is a(n unfinished) sketch of some of this on my personal web here. (Do ask if you’d like to know more; I intend to flesh this out when I get time.)

    Here’s what I’m not doing (this is all due to Pieter Hofstra): say you start with a pca AA, e.g. the naturals with Kleene application. You can form an indexed poset that I’ll call Set(,A)Set(-,A) (even though the ordering is not the pointwise one but the ’realizability’ one). The category of elements of this is the category of partitioned assemblies over AA. For any pca AA, the sets PAP A and P *AP_* A of subsets and non-empty subsets of AA are again pcas and give indexed posets in the same way; the category of elements of Set(,P *A)Set(-,P_* A) is the category of assemblies over AA, while Set(,PA)Set(-,P A) is the realizability tripos over AA.

    This last is a regular fibration, so corresponds to (what I call) a framed bicategory of relations, and the (underlying bicategory of the) coreflexive splitting of the latter is Rel of the category of assemblies over AA. From that point on, the two paths coincide. (I’d very much like to understand the earlier parts of the two processes better, but then I’d also like to finish my thesis sometime this decade…)

    • CommentRowNumber12.
    • CommentAuthorZhen Lin
    • CommentTimeFeb 22nd 2013
    • (edited Feb 22nd 2013)

    @Todd:

    Johnstone (in Definition F2.2.4) uses “exemplary element” instead of “generic predicate” or “generic element”. The definition is for a 𝒞\mathcal{C}-indexed preorder 𝕋\mathbb{T}, where 𝒞\mathcal{C} is cartesian closed: an exemplary element is an element ξ𝒯 Ξ\xi \in \mathcal{T}^\Xi for some Ξob𝒞\Xi \in \operatorname{ob} \mathcal{C} such that, for each Iob𝒞I \in \operatorname{ob} \mathcal{C}, every object in 𝒯 I\mathcal{T}^I is isomorphic to x *(ξ)x^*(\xi) for some (not necessarily unique) x:IΞx : I \to \Xi.

    Surely, the construction I suggested converts generic proofs into generic predicates? First of all, the preorder reflection is a 2-functor ℭ𝔞𝔱𝔓𝔯𝔢𝔬𝔯𝔡\mathfrak{Cat} \to \mathfrak{Preord}, so we can certainly do a fibrewise preorder reflection on any indexed category 𝔼\mathbb{E}; call it \mathbb{P} for now. If 𝔼\mathbb{E} is the self-indexing of a regular category 𝒞\mathcal{C} with the axiom of choice then this should be equivalent to the indexed preorder 𝕊ub(𝒞)\mathbb{S}ub (\mathcal{C}), by the observations at generic proof, and otherwise it’s some kind of souped-up version of 𝕊ub(𝔼)\mathbb{S}ub (\mathbb{E}). Regardless, a generic proof in 𝔼\mathbb{E} is precisely an object Θ\Theta in a fibre Λ\mathcal{E}^\Lambda such that Θ\Theta, regarded as an object in 𝒫 Λ\mathcal{P}^\Lambda, is a generic predicate in \mathbb{P}.

    • CommentRowNumber13.
    • CommentAuthorMike Shulman
    • CommentTimeFeb 22nd 2013

    Whoa, Part F exists now? Where can I find it?

    • CommentRowNumber14.
    • CommentAuthorZhen Lin
    • CommentTimeFeb 22nd 2013

    I’m not sure if Part F exists in full, but Johnstone is basically lecturing Chapter F2 as a graduate course in Cambridge this term. Perhaps he might email you a copy if you ask? All I have (so far) are paper printouts of the first three sections. Parts of Chapter F1 have also been written up, at least according to a fellow student who works in synthetic differential geometry.

    • CommentRowNumber15.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeFeb 22nd 2013

    I have now replaced the other tentative assertion in the section axioms of choice with something more definitive: another paper of Menni’s shows that the exact completion of a Boolean Grothendieck topos with enough points is also a topos.

    • CommentRowNumber16.
    • CommentAuthorMike Shulman
    • CommentTimeFeb 22nd 2013

    @Zhen: Cool! I’ll probably wait for the final version; I don’t exactly need more reading material right now.