Want to take part in these discussions? Sign in if you have an account, or apply for one below
Vanilla 1.1.10 is a product of Lussumo. More Information: Documentation, Community Support.
1 to 2 of 2
I’m trying to expand a little bit on the page about -ary factorization systems. In particular I want to understand the “convergence condition” given by
I can understand that this is an abstraction of what happens in the finite case, where every -ary factorization system (for ) can be thought “completed” by
Nevertheless it seems to me that the whole situation deserves a more subtle analysis. Let me switch to a less peculiar notation to denote the factorization of an arrow ( and are a bit misleading to my eye).
I agree that a -stage FS in should consist of a functor (where I’m regarding both the poset/ordinal and as categories). This entails that for any there is a factorization
Now we would like to impose four “convergence conditions” on these factorizations, which play the role of and :
(all the limits and colimits are taken over the various slice/coslice categories). Now, an asimmetry arises: it’s rather easy to compute colimits in a slice category [resp. limits in a coslice category], since they are computed as colimits (resp., limits) in the underlying category: the natural forgetful functor (resp., ) reflects limits (resp., colimits). Conversely, limits in a slice category (resp., colimits in a coslice category) tend to be more complicated to compute.
In fact, not so complicated: it can be shown that the above forgetful functors reflect also connected limits/colimits (depending on the side where you slice).
My first question is: the nLan page is rather obscure in this part. Is connectedness the main reason why we choose ordinals as indices for -ary factorization systems? When the author says
Fix any ordinal number (or opposite thereof, or any poset, really)
does (s?)he mean, instead, any connected poset, really? If not, arguing in general, I don’t see how it is possible to resolve the “skewness” between the limit of a diagram computed in a slice category, and the limit of the functor projected to the base. But maybe it’s my fault! Please, follow my computation…
In general, it is a matter of verifying universal property the proof that
where is the category which is forced to have an (additional) initial object, and is the extension of the functor with value on the unique object of . The RHS colimit inherits a canonical arrow , which turns it into an object of .
A completely dual result characterizes limits in a slice category:
Now, I would like to know if one can say something more in this general case. In the diagram
the limit arrows have no reason to be adjacent, and more in general it is not possible to compare and in the right direction (but there is an arrow –dually, –).
In order to fix this, one should pray either for the existence of a (hopefully canonical) arrow
such that the composition equals the we started with, or for the existence of a similar comparison .
Let’s concentrate on the first case. How about the existence of such an arrow? Well, it relies on a rather peculiar property of the index category :
any two objects can be connected by an arrow, either or
(which is stronger than being connected), since if this happens we can define an arrow as for some : this choice doesn’t affect the definition of since the diagram
commutes for any two . A total order is a typical (easy) example of a category satisfying this property (“every two objects can be compared”), so in the case of a totally ordered family of factorization systems I’m left with checking that the composition
coincides with ; fortunately this is a trivial exercise in pasting commutative triangles.
This is where I stopped. Am I going in the right direction? Is condition also necessary, or rather we fall again in the realm of connected categories?
1 to 2 of 2