Not signed in (Sign In)

Not signed in

Want to take part in these discussions? Sign in if you have an account, or apply for one below

  • Sign in using OpenID

Site Tag Cloud

2-category 2-category-theory abelian-categories adjoint algebra algebraic algebraic-geometry algebraic-topology analysis analytic-geometry arithmetic arithmetic-geometry book bundles calculus categorical categories category category-theory chern-weil-theory cohesion cohesive-homotopy-type-theory cohomology colimits combinatorics complex complex-geometry computable-mathematics computer-science constructive cosmology deformation-theory descent diagrams differential differential-cohomology differential-equations differential-geometry digraphs duality elliptic-cohomology enriched fibration foundation foundations functional-analysis functor gauge-theory gebra geometric-quantization geometry graph graphs gravity grothendieck group group-theory harmonic-analysis higher higher-algebra higher-category-theory higher-differential-geometry higher-geometry higher-lie-theory higher-topos-theory homological homological-algebra homotopy homotopy-theory homotopy-type-theory index-theory integration integration-theory k-theory lie-theory limits linear linear-algebra locale localization logic mathematics measure-theory modal modal-logic model model-category-theory monad monads monoidal monoidal-category-theory morphism motives motivic-cohomology nforum nlab noncommutative noncommutative-geometry number-theory of operads operator operator-algebra order-theory pages pasting philosophy physics pro-object probability probability-theory quantization quantum quantum-field quantum-field-theory quantum-mechanics quantum-physics quantum-theory question representation representation-theory riemannian-geometry scheme schemes set set-theory sheaf sheaves simplicial space spin-geometry stable-homotopy-theory stack string string-theory superalgebra supergeometry svg symplectic-geometry synthetic-differential-geometry terminology theory topology topos topos-theory tqft type type-theory universal variational-calculus

Vanilla 1.1.10 is a product of Lussumo. More Information: Documentation, Community Support.

Welcome to nForum
If you want to take part in these discussions either sign in now (if you have an account), apply for one now (if you don't).
    • CommentRowNumber1.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeJan 11th 2015
    • (edited Jan 11th 2015)

    In some topos H\mathbf{H}, consider some property PP on morphisms f:ABf \colon A \to B (such as being an equivalence, being étale, …), and consider the question of forming “the” (sub-)object [A,B] P[A,B]_P of the internal hom [A,B][A,B] on those maps satisfying this condition.

    Consider then the special case that H\mathbf{H} is local with sharp modality \sharp. Then a candidate for the internal [A,B] P[A,B]_P is the fiber product H(A,B) P×[A,B][A,B]\mathbf{H}(A,B)_P\underset{\sharp [A,B]}{\times} [A,B].

    (Here H(A,B) PH(A,B)\mathbf{H}(A,B)_P \hookrightarrow \mathbf{H}(A,B) denotes the external space of maps satisfying PP, regarded as “codiscretely” embedded back into H\mathbf{H}.)

    Is that fiber product equivalent to what one ends up with a formulation of [A,B] P[A,B]_P in the internal logic?

    • CommentRowNumber2.
    • CommentAuthorMike Shulman
    • CommentTimeJan 12th 2015

    Interesting question; I think the answer is no. A map f:X[A,B]f:X\to [A,B] corresponds to a map f^:X×AB\hat{f} : X\times A \to B, hence to a map f¯:X×AX×B\bar{f}:X\times A \to X\times B in H/X\mathbf{H}/X, and ff factors through Equiv(A,B)Equiv(A,B) just when f¯\bar{f} is an equivalence in H/X\mathbf{H}/X. But I think ff will factor through your fiber product just when the fiber of f¯\bar{f} over each point of XX is an equivalence, which is a weaker statement.

    • CommentRowNumber3.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeJan 12th 2015

    Yes, true, what I wrote sees only the global points. But assuming that AA and BB and hence also [A,B][A,B] are concrete, then it should work, right?

    • CommentRowNumber4.
    • CommentAuthorMike Shulman
    • CommentTimeJan 12th 2015

    Why does concreteness of AA and BB help? It seems to me like the problem is possible non-concreteness (or maybe non-co-concreteness) of XX.

    • CommentRowNumber5.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeJan 12th 2015
    • (edited Jan 12th 2015)

    So if AA and BB are concrete, then so is [A,B][A,B] and hence maps into it are characterized by maps into [A,B]\sharp [A,B], which are maps into [A,B][A,B] out of ()\flat(-), hence out of all points of the domain.

    • CommentRowNumber6.
    • CommentAuthorMike Shulman
    • CommentTimeJan 12th 2015

    Where by “characterized by” you mean that the map from X[A,B]X\to [A,B] to X[A,B]X\to \sharp [A,B] is monic, so that two maps X[A,B]X\to [A,B] are equal as soon as they become so when postcomposing with [A,B][A,B][A,B]\to \sharp [A,B]; hence two maps X×AX×BX\times A\to X\times B over XX are equal as soon as they become so after pulling back along XX\flat X\to X. Right? Why does that imply that a single map X×AX×BX\times A\to X\times B over XX is an equivalence as soon as it becomes so after pulling back to X\flat X? A priori it seems that its inverse X×BX×A\flat X\times B\to \flat X\times A might not come from any map over XX.

    • CommentRowNumber7.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeJan 15th 2015

    I see, thanks!