Not signed in (Sign In)

Not signed in

Want to take part in these discussions? Sign in if you have an account, or apply for one below

  • Sign in using OpenID

Site Tag Cloud

2-category 2-category-theory abelian-categories adjoint algebra algebraic algebraic-geometry algebraic-topology analysis analytic-geometry arithmetic arithmetic-geometry book bundles calculus categorical categories category category-theory chern-weil-theory cohesion cohesive-homotopy-type-theory cohomology colimits combinatorics complex complex-geometry computable-mathematics computer-science constructive cosmology deformation-theory descent diagrams differential differential-cohomology differential-equations differential-geometry digraphs duality elliptic-cohomology enriched fibration foundation foundations functional-analysis functor gauge-theory gebra geometric-quantization geometry graph graphs gravity grothendieck group group-theory harmonic-analysis higher higher-algebra higher-category-theory higher-differential-geometry higher-geometry higher-lie-theory higher-topos-theory homological homological-algebra homotopy homotopy-theory homotopy-type-theory index-theory integration integration-theory internal-categories k-theory lie-theory limits linear linear-algebra locale localization logic mathematics measure measure-theory modal modal-logic model model-category-theory monad monads monoidal monoidal-category-theory morphism motives motivic-cohomology nlab noncommutative noncommutative-geometry number-theory of operads operator operator-algebra order-theory pages pasting philosophy physics pro-object probability probability-theory quantization quantum quantum-field quantum-field-theory quantum-mechanics quantum-physics quantum-theory question representation representation-theory riemannian-geometry scheme schemes set set-theory sheaf simplicial space spin-geometry stable-homotopy-theory stack string string-theory superalgebra supergeometry svg symplectic-geometry synthetic-differential-geometry terminology theory topology topos topos-theory tqft type type-theory universal variational-calculus

Vanilla 1.1.10 is a product of Lussumo. More Information: Documentation, Community Support.

Welcome to nForum
If you want to take part in these discussions either sign in now (if you have an account), apply for one now (if you don't).
    • CommentRowNumber1.
    • CommentAuthorEric
    • CommentTimeMay 23rd 2010

    David just pointed out an article that looks very interesting even after just reading the first few paragraphs. I thought I’d go ahead and start a discussion on this paper

    Abstract: This article gives a conceptual introduction to the topos approach to the formulation of physical theories.

    Here’s the first few paragraphs of the introductions:

    Introduction

    Over forty years have passed since I first became interested in the problem of quantum gravity. During that time there have been many diversions and, perhaps, some advances. Certainly, the naively-optimistic approaches have long been laid to rest, and the schemes that remain have achieved some degree of stability. The original ‘canonical’ programme evolved into loop quantum gravity, which has become one of the two major approaches. The other, of course, is string theory—a scheme whose roots lie in the old Veneziano model of hadronic interactions, but whose true value became apparent only after it had been re-conceived as a theory of quantum gravity.

    However, notwithstanding these hard-won developments, there are certain issues in quantum gravity that transcend any of the current schemes. These involve deep problems of both a mathematical and a philosophical kind, and stem from a fundamental paradigm clash between general relativity—the apotheosis of classical physics—and quantum physics.

    In general relativity, space-time ’itself’ is modelled by a differentiable manifold \mathcal{M}: a set whose elements are interpreted as ’space-time points’. The curvature tensor of the pseudo-Riemannian metric on \mathcal{M} is then deemed to represent the gravitational field. As a classical theory, the underlying philosophical interpretation is realist: both the space-time and its points truly ‘exist’\footnote{At least, that would be the view of unreconstructed, space-time substantivalists. However, even purely within the realm of classical physics this position has often been challenged, particularly by those who place emphasis on the relational features that are inherent in general relativity.}, as does the gravitational field.

    On the other hand, standard quantum theory employs a background space-time that is fixed ab initio in regard to both its differential structure and its metric/curvature. Furthermore, the conventional interpretation is thoroughly instrumentalist in nature, dealing as it does with counter-factual statements about what would happen (or, to be more precise, the probability of what would happen) if a measurement is made of some physical quantity.

    • CommentRowNumber2.
    • CommentAuthorIan_Durham
    • CommentTimeMay 24th 2010
    In starting to read this, I think I just discovered another source of our original misunderstanding over spacetime (paragraph 3). For one reason or another I have always thought of the metric as being ontologically associated with the topology of the manifold whereas Isham makes a clear distinction between the spacetime, as represented by the space-time points (what I, as a relationalist, would call `events' though perhaps that's too solipsistic), and the gravitational field, as represented by the curvature tensor. I find some solace in his first footnote. I would count myself as one of those challengers he mentions. :-)
    • CommentRowNumber3.
    • CommentAuthorEric
    • CommentTimeMay 24th 2010

    It makes sense to distinguish what is purely topological from what is metrical. The metric is a tensor field sitting on the smooth manifold. Maxwell’s equations provide a good example.

    The expression

    dF=0d F = 0

    is purely topological. It is defined even if you don’t have a metric at all. This represents two of four Maxwell’s field equations (×E+Bt=0\nabla\times E + \frac{\partial B}{\partial t} = 0 and .B=0\nabla . B = 0).

    The expression

    dG=jd G = j

    is also purely topological. This represents the other two Maxwell field equations (×HDt=J\nabla\times H - \frac{\partial D}{\partial t} = J and .D=ϱ\nabla . D = \varrho).

    The metric is needed to link FF and GG (via the constitutive relations)

    G=FG = \star F

    giving D=εED = \epsilon E and B=μHB = \mu H.

    • CommentRowNumber4.
    • CommentAuthorIan_Durham
    • CommentTimeMay 24th 2010
    I really do need to learn some topology. Harry gave me some references awhile back but I have since misplaced them.
    • CommentRowNumber5.
    • CommentAuthorDavidRoberts
    • CommentTimeMay 24th 2010
    • (edited May 24th 2010)

    You probably don’t want to learn point-set topology - it’s full of gnarly things you wouldn’t want to meet in a dark alley (like the long circle - it’s sort of like a circle, but ’infinitely long’, so that no map from an ordinary circle can wrap around it. Or the Warsaw circle, which is connected, but has points that don’t have connected neighbourhoods, and again an ordinary circle can’t wrap around it, even though it cuts the plane into two regions). Hatcher’s book Algebraic Topology is free and quite good (you don’t need the stuff towards the end, I wager, but I used it to construct a toy spacetime in which to look at string theory’s T-duality in my honours thesis) Or Ronnie Brown’s book on topology is very cheap (£5!) for an electronic copy - you can buy a hardcopy as well - and this is very good for basic topology. I used it as a constant reminder of things for my PhD thesis that I was slow in absorbing.

    • CommentRowNumber6.
    • CommentAuthorEric
    • CommentTimeMay 24th 2010
    • (edited May 24th 2010)

    I wouldn’t suggest it as a general reference for learning topology, but the first part of my dissertation was designed specifically to introduce (and motivate) topology to “scientists and engineers”.

    PS: I received good feedback specifically on the motivating Introduction from Richard Bishop (yes, the Richard Bishop) and Stephanie Alexander (who was on my committee and still my all time favorite professor who taught me elementary differential geometry). I think you might like it too.

    • CommentRowNumber7.
    • CommentAuthorDavidRoberts
    • CommentTimeMay 24th 2010

    @Eric,

    the link to your dissertation goes to the nLab at the moment, instead of your private web, where I imagine it should have gone.

    • CommentRowNumber8.
    • CommentAuthorEric
    • CommentTimeMay 24th 2010

    Thanks David. Fixed.

    • CommentRowNumber9.
    • CommentAuthorIan_Durham
    • CommentTimeMay 24th 2010
    Thanks for the references, guys.

    I'm through the first couple of sections of Isham's paper, by the way. Got sidetracked by the Lost finale, but I do have some comments I'll post in the morning when I'm less tired.
    • CommentRowNumber10.
    • CommentAuthorHarry Gindi
    • CommentTimeMay 24th 2010
    • (edited May 24th 2010)

    @DavidRoberts:

    You probably don’t want to learn point-set topology - it’s full of gnarly things you wouldn’t want to meet in a dark alley (like the long circle - it’s sort of like a circle, but ’infinitely long’, so that no map from an ordinary circle can wrap around it. Or the Warsaw circle, which is connected, but has points that don’t have connected neighbourhoods, and again an ordinary circle can’t wrap around it, even though it cuts the plane into two regions). Hatcher’s book Algebraic Topology is free and quite good (you don’t need the stuff towards the end, I wager, but I used it to construct a toy spacetime in which to look at string theory’s T-duality in my honours thesis) Or Ronnie Brown’s book on topology is very cheap (£5!) for an electronic copy - you can buy a hardcopy as well - and this is very good for basic topology. I used it as a constant reminder of things for my PhD thesis that I was slow in absorbing.

    I disagree with you for the following reason: there are basic skills in point-set topology that one needs to understand before progressing. Things like the product topology, the quotient topology, at least the axioms T0, T1, and T2, the many equivalent formulations of continuity, closures, supports, compactness, convergence, metric spaces, topological equivalence of metrics, uniform equivalence of metrics, isometries, product and quotient metrics, retractions, injective homeomorphisms, and the list goes on. These are important technical aspects of point-set topology that are used all the time in the more “interesting” areas of topology.

    @Ian: I suggested one of the following three books:

    General Topology by John L. Kelley

    Topology by Munkres

    Topologie Generale by Nicolas Bourbaki.

    I believe I ranked them as follows: Easiest read - Munkres, Most citations (over a thousand!) - Kelley, Sheer clarity of presentation - Bourbaki.

    You’ve said in the past that you’re rather comfortable with elementary modern algebra, which leads me to believe that Bourbaki would actually be the best fit for you. My philosophy for books on modern algebra and general topology is that if you can read Bourbaki (without struggling too much), then you should, simply because the books are a work of art (the proofs are always clear and concise, but never slick).

    Please e-mail me at harry.gindi ([{AT}]) gmail.com, and I can provide you with electronic copies of all three books.

    • CommentRowNumber11.
    • CommentAuthorTim_van_Beek
    • CommentTimeMay 24th 2010

    Ian said:

    I really do need to learn some topology.

    and David answered:

    You probably don’t want to learn point-set topology - it’s full of gnarly things you wouldn’t want to meet in a dark alley…

    I think what David wanted to warn you about is that the notion of “topological space” is very general, and general point-set topology is about all the “pathological” situations that tend to fascinate mathematicians and are deemed irrelevant by physicists, much like the difference of smooth and analytical, or that of the Riemann and the Lesbegue integral.

    Is there a specific topic that you would like to learn something about?

    Like, for example: “I would like to understand Connes’ work on the standard model, would like to understand his book ’Noncommutative Geometry’ for that reason, keep running into ’fribrations’, what is that?”. It would be easier to point out some literature if I knew what you are up to.

    • CommentRowNumber12.
    • CommentAuthorHarry Gindi
    • CommentTimeMay 24th 2010

    @Tim: I’m not saying that Ian should read these books front to back. That would be crazy. However, many arguments in functional analysis and differential geometry (I assume that this is what Ian is really interested in from a physics perspective) rely on a fairly solid understanding of most of the things that I noted above.

    • CommentRowNumber13.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeMay 24th 2010

    Point-set topology is a fine thing to learn. Munkres’s book is a nice gentle introduction at an undergraduate level, but is solidly written and rather free from errors. I wish it were written in a more categorical spirit (which really explains why, e.g., products and quotients have the topologies they do), and I personally believe there is undue emphasis on things like necessary and sufficient conditions for metrizability, but that’s as may be. In fact, all the books Harry recommended are good.

    It’s possible and maybe even tempting to teach point-set topology with rather a heavy emphasis on pathology, but that would be a mistake, and I don’t see that this is what the subject is actually about. On the other hand, core notions like connectedness, compactness, and separation axioms are indispensable, as are basic constructions – every mathematician should know them.

    • CommentRowNumber14.
    • CommentAuthorHarry Gindi
    • CommentTimeMay 24th 2010
    • (edited May 24th 2010)

    It’s possible and maybe even tempting to teach point-set topology with rather a heavy emphasis on pathology, but that would be a mistake, and I don’t see that this is what the subject is actually about. On the other hand, core notions like connectedness, compactness, and separation axioms are indispensable, as are basic constructions – every mathematician should know them.

    Absolutely! Pathological examples should only be studied as far as they explain the necessity of hypotheses. It seems like point-set topology has gained a bad reputation for having so many such examples, but this really only serves to demonstrate how the early development of topology proceeded. The definition of a topological space is an abstraction of the definition of a metric space. Once they discovered this definition, the early topologists set to work finding sufficient conditions over and above the definition of a topological space from which we could derive the properties of euclidean space.

    Contrast this with algebra. Most theorems in algebra are not proven first from minimal conditions over the core axioms. Rather, theorems are often proven in the simplest case (for example, over algebraically closed fields) then extended to more general cases by reducing the problem to the case that is already known.

    Point-set topology doesn’t lend itself nearly as well to such reductions. Since we are trying to generalize the important properties of euclidean space, which is a very very special space, we can’t often prove things by reduction to the case of euclidean space, so we’re forced to move ahead and develop things from the bottom up. The pathological examples in topology are essentially justifications of the separation axioms. They were much more important to the development of point-set topology than to the study of the subject in the modern day.

    • CommentRowNumber15.
    • CommentAuthorIan_Durham
    • CommentTimeMay 24th 2010
    • (edited May 24th 2010)
    @Tim: So I understand what a basic topological space is, but I'd like a deeper understanding of it in order to better understand its nuances. I think Harry has a handle on what I need to learn (he's been arguing with me for a long enough time now :-)).

    @Harry: Thanks. I sent you an e-mail.

    Now, as for Isham's paper, I'm through section 3.1 so far. I think his overall approach - looking for a totally new formalism instead of trying to duct-tape together the existing formalisms of QM and GR - is exactly what is needed for a true theory of quantum gravity. I have two major issues so far:

    1. He says quantum gravity is lacking the experimental data portion of the "unholy trinity" as he calls it. But regular quantum mechanics is lacking the conceptual portion (which is why we have so many "interpretations" - if we had a conceptual portion, we wouldn't need interpretations or, rather, there would only be one). So quantum gravity is ultimately lacking two of the parts of his "unholy trinity."

    2. While he ultimately may be correct in saying that we need to dispense with real-numbered assumptions, he seems to gloss over the fact (notably in the second paragraph of section 2) that we have good reason to rely on them since that is how we experience the world (if you read a history of mathematics text - a good one - you get a sense for how closely real numbers are tied to human experience). This fact can't be glossed over. Somehow this experiential aspect needs to fit into his overall scheme. On the other hand, I think it is possible to tie experience to a Boolean algebra (which he concludes is the mathematical structure of classical physics) fairly easily.

    One additional minor point: in section 3.1 he defines the "states" of a system as being the mathematical entities that determine "the way things are." While this may be a (the) common interpretation, I am not convinced it is correct. I believe the state of a system to be independent of any mathematical structure we may impose upon it (unless one believes that certain parts of mathematics are "real" and not merely a formal model). I have to think some more about his fourth point there (properties of the system).

    I'll be honest and say I'd never heard the word "margaritiferous" before. :-) And the aside concerning the exchange between Wheeler and Dirac was great.
    • CommentRowNumber16.
    • CommentAuthorTim_van_Beek
    • CommentTimeMay 24th 2010
    • (edited May 24th 2010)

    I’ll be honest and say I’d never heard the word “margaritiferous” before.

    Darn! I had hoped someone could explain that to me.

    He says quantum gravity is lacking the experimental data portion of the “unholy trinity” as he calls it.

    Sometimes you first need a theory to be able to formulate new questions, with answers that can support or falsify your theory. Take QM itself: If you are restricted to non-relativistic systems you will never find any facts that contradict it: you would need to find a physical system and prove that there cannot be any Hamiltonian at all such that the time evolution is described by the Schrödinger equation. I don’t think that this is possible. If you take special relativity into the account, you see that 1.QM violates causality and 2. cannot describe particle creation and annihilation. To see that QM cannot be the end of the story you don’t need any experiments that show 1., the theoretical fact of a contradiction should be enough to motivate the development of a new theory…

    While he ultimately may be correct in saying that we need to dispense with real-numbered assumptions, he seems to gloss over the fact…that we have good reason to rely on them since that is how we experience the world…

    But we can measure rational numbers only, not real ones.

    From Chris Isham’s paper:

    The Kochen-Specker theorem is equivalent to the statement that the spectral presheaf has no global elements.

    Now that statement should go to a nLab page, shouldn’t it? (Yeah I know, but I don’t think that I understand both the classical theorem and its Isham-reformulation well enough yet).

    • CommentRowNumber17.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeMay 24th 2010

    We had had some discussion of the sheaf-theoretic interpretation of Kochen Specker in old blog discussion, such as here. I agree that it would be nice to turn this stuff into nLab entries. I don’t have time for it right now, though…

    • CommentRowNumber18.
    • CommentAuthorIan_Durham
    • CommentTimeMay 24th 2010
    Apparently "margaritiferous" means something like "producing pearls." This is not to be confused with "margaritiferus" which is part of the Latin name for several species of non-venomous snake.

    the theoretical fact of a contradiction should be enough to motivate the development of a new theory...



    I don't disagree. My point was simply that quantum gravity (as with QM) lacks a single, consistent conceptual description. I think in the case of quantum gravity, we may have no choice but to pursue the route that your comment suggests since it may be unclear whether it is even possible to perform certain measurements on spacetime itself.

    But we can measure rational numbers only, not real ones.



    I was assuming his point was to distinguish between the real-numbered classical world and the complex-numbered quantum world. We, as human beings, experience the real-numbered world through measurements of rational numbers (and, in theory, couldn't you say we can indirectly measure irrational numbers as well via ratios?).

    If y'all are ok with it, I'll create a page for Kochen-Specker.
    • CommentRowNumber19.
    • CommentAuthorDavidRoberts
    • CommentTimeMay 25th 2010

    measure irrational numbers as well via ratios

    ???? ratios of what? All we measure are finitely long decimal expansions, and ratios of these are also finitely long. This does depend on one’s choice of units, of course. There nothing to say one can’t define the length 1 Michael* = π\pi cm, and by measuring 1.254336 cm, then this is an irrational number of Michaels. But this is silly (*Michael is my middle name, ’Davids’ or ’Robertses’ sounds silly)

    • CommentRowNumber20.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeMay 25th 2010

    I’m not following this discussion closely; just writing to mention there was Café discussion on this topic here, including some discussion of Kochen-Specker. I don’t think this blog post was mentioned yet.

    • CommentRowNumber21.
    • CommentAuthorIan_Durham
    • CommentTimeMay 25th 2010

    ???? ratios of what? All we measure are finitely long decimal expansions, and ratios of these are also finitely long.



    Right, nevermind. I was thinking of pi specifically in terms of circumference and diameter, but that's quite obviously a dumb idea in retrospect.

    (`Davids' and `Robertses' makes you sound like Gollum...)
    • CommentRowNumber22.
    • CommentAuthorTim_van_Beek
    • CommentTimeMay 25th 2010

    Todd said:

    I’m not following this discussion closely; just writing to mention there was Café discussion on this topic here, including some discussion of Kochen-Specker. I don’t think this blog post was mentioned yet.

    Urs did, although I have to admit that I did not have a look at Isham’s papers mentioned there - so the Kochen-Specker theorem fails in two dimensions just like Gleason’s theorem? I’m sure that is connected in some way or another…

    • CommentRowNumber23.
    • CommentAuthorDavidRoberts
    • CommentTimeMay 25th 2010

    http://arxiv.org/abs/1005.4172 - the article aims at recovering special relativity from the purely causal structure of spacetime i.e. as a poset (perhaps with some structure). This certainly seems up Eric’s alley, and possibly Ian’s

    • CommentRowNumber24.
    • CommentAuthorHarry Gindi
    • CommentTimeMay 25th 2010

    @Ian: I just want to note another very cool approach taken by Bourbaki:

    Chapters 1 and 2 cover topological and uniform structures respectively and give axiomatic descriptions of such spaces.

    Chapter 3 covers the theory of topological groups.

    Chapter 4 applies the results of chapters 1 and 2 to construct from scratch the real line, which is not used explicitly or implicitly in any of the preceding chapters or even the preceding books. I find this extremely appealing.

    • CommentRowNumber25.
    • CommentAuthorEric
    • CommentTimeMay 25th 2010

    @David: Yeah, I haven’t looked at the paper yet, but the idea is not new. It goes back at least 20 years. I’ll try to find some references.

    The ingredients you need to construct Minkowski space are (roughly)

    1. a poset
    2. a measure

    Thanks to the Leinster measure, I think you really only need a poset now. This is so cool, I wish it was taught to undergrads.

    • CommentRowNumber26.
    • CommentAuthorHarry Gindi
    • CommentTimeMay 25th 2010
    • (edited May 25th 2010)

    @Eric: That’s not true unless you’re using a nonstandard definition of a Minkowski space.

    Ingredients you need to construct a Minkowski space are: An R-vector space of dimension n and a symmetric nondegenerate bilinear form of signature (n-1,1,0). Note that Sylvester’s classification law does not hold over general fields (for instance, it is patently false for the rational numbers, and over the complex numbers, the signature is even simpler).

    • CommentRowNumber27.
    • CommentAuthorEric
    • CommentTimeMay 25th 2010

    Here are some references

    One of the earliest (if not the earliest) paper to discuss this is

    • L. Bombelli, Space-time as a Causal Set, Ph.D. thesis, Syracuse University (1987)
    • CommentRowNumber28.
    • CommentAuthorTim_van_Beek
    • CommentTimeMay 25th 2010

    Eric said:

    Thanks to the Leinster measure, I think you really only need a poset now.

    Unfortunatly I did not follow that discussion, I suppose that the nCafé thread that Leinster measure redirects to is still the best place to start?

    Harry said:

    Ingredients you need to construct a Minkowski space are:…

    I think Eric alluded to the game “taking the classical limit” of some “quantum system”, which has floating rules, usually you are not restricted to use the ingredients of your quantum system only, you may take all sorts of approximations :-)

    • CommentRowNumber29.
    • CommentAuthorEric
    • CommentTimeMay 25th 2010
    • (edited May 25th 2010)

    I’m pretty sure you can construct Minkowski space from the causal structure (poset) and a measure. If it were trivially obvious, it wouldn’t be “so cool” :)

    The poset itself gives you Minkowski space up to a conformal transformation. The measure ties down the conformal transformation. I don’t know if anyone has gone ahead and proved it with Leinster measure, but I have very little doubt the math will go through as promised.

    Roughly, you start with 4\mathbb{R}^4 and define a (causal) relation between points. This determines the Minkowski metric up to a conformal transformation. If you specify a measure, you get the Minkowski metric. It would be interesting to determine the Leinster measure of this poset and see if it gives the correct Minkowski metric.

    I would lose faith in the universe if the Leinster measure does not give the correct metric :)

    • CommentRowNumber30.
    • CommentAuthorEric
    • CommentTimeMay 25th 2010

    Here is a blurb Urs wrote on smooth Lorentzian space:

    Being causal means being a poset

    Precisely if the Lorentzian space is causal in that there are no closed future-directed curves is the relation

    • (xy)(x \leq y) \Leftrightarrowyy is in the future of xx

    a poset, hence a category with at most a single morphism between any two objects:

    The objects of this category are the points of XX. A morphism xyx \to y is a pair of points xyx \leq y with yy in the future of xx. Composition of morphisms is transitivity of the relation. The identity morphism on xx is the reflexivity xxx \leq x.

    The anti-symmetry (xyx)(x=y)(x \leq y \leq x) \Rightarrow (x = y) is precisely the absence of closed future-directed curves in XX.

    Conversely, from just knowing XX as a smooth manifold and knowing this poset structure on XX, one can reeconstruct the light cone structure of (X,μ)(X,\mu), i.e. the information about which tangent vectors are timelike, lightlike, etc.

    One can see

    (…reference…)

    that the pseudo-Riemannian metric μ\mu may be reconstructed from the lightcone structure and the volume density that it induces. In this sense a Lorentzian manifold without future-directed curves is equivalently a smooth poset equipped with a smooth measure on its space of objects.

    It looks like I might be confusing “conformal structure” with “light cone structure”.

    This is a very pretty factoid and I’d highly recommend tracking some references to get the story straight. I’m going from memory and I didn’t completely understand it the first time around :)

    • CommentRowNumber31.
    • CommentAuthorEric
    • CommentTimeMay 25th 2010

    Oh right. Here is the Discussion from smooth Lorentzian space

    Discussion

    A previous version of this entry started the following discussion.

    Toby asked: How does this relate to a (smooth) Lorentzian manifold? if at all.

    Eric says: Good question. I took the statement from a comment Urs made here. I chose to use the word “space” instead of “manifold” simply because it seemed to fit into a theme here about generalized smooth “spaces”. The definition definitely needs fleshing out, but its a start.

    Urs:

    The point is: there is a theorem

    that says that a map between two Lorentzian manifolds which preserves the causal structure, i.e. which is a functor of the underlying posets, is automatically a conformal isometry. There is, I think, another related theorem which says that from just the lightcone structure of a Lorentzian manifold, one can reconstruct its Lorentzian metric up to a conformal rescaling.

    Both theorems suggest that a Lorentzian metric on a manifold is in a way equivalent to a pair consisting of a measure on the manifold and lightcone structure. The latter in turn can be encoded in a poset structure on the manifold. If true, it would seem to suggest that a good foundational model for relativistic physics might be posets internal to Meas.

    Somebody should sort this out.

    Eric says: I like this idea. The measure could be the Leinster measure, which would be neat. We discussed this before at the nCafe I think.

    Urs: Yes, exactly. There was the idea that, since many finite categories come with a canonical measure on their space (set) of objects, maybe we somehow need to merge this idea of Leinster measure with the idea of modelling a Lorentzain spacetime by something like a poset. Playing around with this observation was the content of this blog entry. But I am not sure if it works out…

    • CommentRowNumber32.
    • CommentAuthorTim_van_Beek
    • CommentTimeMay 25th 2010

    You know, I have no problem with the other direction: All that is objective in Minkowski space are the causal relationsships of events (poset) and - after agreeing on a clock device - the proper time of observers (measure?). Intuitively it seems perfectly obvious. But on the other hand I never got my intuition to tell me something as simple as what the commutator of two observables in QM should be, so I don’t trust it.

    • CommentRowNumber33.
    • CommentAuthorIan_Durham
    • CommentTimeMay 25th 2010
    @Harry: And despite having eight of Bourbaki's works, it figures the one our library doesn't have is the one you mentioned (we do have the other two you mentioned, though). Looks like I'll be hitting up Interlibrary Loan (and maybe spending some of my annual library budget...). :-) I have seen various constructions of the real line, but none were topological.

    But on the other hand I never got my intuition to tell me something as simple as what the commutator of two observables in QM should be, so I don't trust it.



    I recently wrote an essay discussing exactly this point. I would be highly skeptical of anyone who said they did reconcile the commutator in QM with intuition.

    It would be interesting to determine the Leinster measure of this poset and see if it gives the correct Minkowski metric.



    Well, there's something else I need to learn. :/

    I will say that it makes sense to me that all you'd need to construct Minkowksi spacetime is a poset and a measure. I mean all you're trying to do is construct the causal structure and then the metric. I guess the tricky part (or maybe it's not that tricky, I don't know) is making sure the metric has the right signature.
    • CommentRowNumber34.
    • CommentAuthorEric
    • CommentTimeMay 25th 2010

    The poset takes care of the signature :)

    • CommentRowNumber35.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeMay 25th 2010
    • (edited May 25th 2010)

    No time, but a small comment:

    to construct a Minkowski spacetime you need no information at all. Because there is a unique Minkowski spacetime for each dimension.

    The statement is that given just the poset structure and the volume density you can reconstruct a general spacetime (subject to some conditions). Such that the poset is the relation “is in the future of” with respect to its metric, and the volume density is the volume density of its metric.

    • CommentRowNumber36.
    • CommentAuthorIan_Durham
    • CommentTimeMay 25th 2010

    The poset takes care of the signature :)



    If you have time, could you explain how the signature pops out of the poset?
    • CommentRowNumber37.
    • CommentAuthorEric
    • CommentTimeMay 25th 2010
    • (edited May 25th 2010)

    Found an online version of Bombelli’s thesis from the Wikipedia page, which has a lot of other interesting looking references.

    PS: Check out the section on “‘t Hooft’s Proposal” in Bombelli’s thesis on page 25

    • CommentRowNumber38.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeMay 25th 2010
    • (edited May 25th 2010)

    The signature of the pseudo-Riemannian space corresponding to some poset is always (-1,1,1,1,…). The morphisms in the poset connect points where one is in the future of the other, with respect to the given metric. The very notion “being in the future of” makes good sense and is defined only for this signature.

    • CommentRowNumber39.
    • CommentAuthorEric
    • CommentTimeMay 25th 2010

    @Ian: Bombelli outlines how this works on pdf page 51 in “Flat Space-Times”.

    This thesis is absolutely beautiful. I can’t believe I never saw this. I’ve always used Bombelli’s published paper for a reference. This is one of those dissertations that gives me hope for humanity :)

    • CommentRowNumber40.
    • CommentAuthorIan_Durham
    • CommentTimeMay 25th 2010
    • (edited May 25th 2010)
    Hmmm. It seems that the signature is at least partially imposed though. In fact in part (j) of the construction he even says that he is imposing the meaning of the conditions in part (i) as a definition of the metric.

    Regarding 't Hooft's proposal, I'm a little confused by something. Bombelli says, "the statement that an element is "greater" than another element is taken to mean that it is causally influenced, i.e. it lies to the future of the latter." (Presumably he meant `influenced by.') Did he also mean to say "it lies in the future lightcone?" Because it is insufficient to merely say that just because one element lies in the future of another they are causally linked (i.e. you can have a space-like separation in which one time coordinate is greater than another). Or maybe he's talking about proper time or the spacetime interval here.
    • CommentRowNumber41.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeMay 25th 2010
    • (edited May 25th 2010)

    Because it is insufficient to merely say that just because one element lies in the future of another they are causally linked (i.e. you can have a space-like separation in which one time coordinate is greater than another). Or maybe he’s talking about proper time or the spacetime interval here.

    All answers are at Lorentzian manifold in the section “Causal structure”.

    • CommentRowNumber42.
    • CommentAuthorEric
    • CommentTimeMay 26th 2010

    @Ian: Before we can communicate we have to agree on the semantics or we will just talk past each other. Let’s try to avoid it here and set some terminology upfront.

    First, the words “in the future” are synonymous with “in the future lightcone”. If an element/event is not in the future lightcone of another element/event, it is not in the future of that event. This is what it means to be causally connected. If two events are not causally connected this way, you cannot tell which one came first. The order would depend on the reference frame. In some reference frame they can even appear to be simultaneous. This is explained pretty nicely on Wikipedia: Relativity of simultaneity. I know you know this, so my purpose for saying it is just to fix the terminology. “In the future” means “in the future lightcone”. I could be wrong, but I get a sense you might be thinking in terms of time coordinates, which is a reasonable way to express a sense of future, i.e. “xx is in the future of yy if t x>t yt_x \gt t_y”, but this would be reference frame dependent. Proper time is only defined for events that are causally connected, i.e. where one event is in the future lightcone of another, so I suppose you could alternatively define “future” in terms of proper time but it would mean the same thing, i.e. “in the future lightcone”.

    This also has ramifications for the maths terminology. We do not say “Spacetime is a totally ordered set”. Only a “partially ordered set” :) For some elements, you cannot determine whether x<yx\lt y or y<xy\lt x. This inability to decide happens precisely when the two events are not causally related, i.e. one is not in the future of the other, i.e. one is not in the future lightcone of the other. Only when events share a lightcone, can you give them an order.

    This is why giving points of a manifold a partial order is equivalent to defining the lightcone. Once you’ve defined the lightcone, you’ve defined the Lorentzian metric up to a “scaling”, i.e. conformal factor. The volume element sets the scale. It is pretty cool. I wish I could check myself, but it’d be neat to check whether the Leinster measure on the poset of spacetime sets the scale so the only input needed would be the poset.

    By the way, Tom and Simon (and I and anyone else who finds their work on “cardinality of a category” fascinating) often wonder aloud about the meaning of “weights”. Skimming Bombelli’s thesis, I think I know what the weight is now. It is (related to) the “probability of having a link” and its integral is “expected number of links”. I’ll need to look up references to match the terms correctly, but the meaning is clear now. See Equation 2.5.1. It is also related to Alexandrov neighborhood.

    • CommentRowNumber43.
    • CommentAuthorIan_Durham
    • CommentTimeMay 26th 2010

    Conversely, from just knowing X as a smooth manifold and knowing this poset structure on X, one can reeconstruct the light cone structure of (X,μ), i.e. the information about which tangent vectors are timelike, lightlike, etc.

    I apologize if this sounds obvious or trivial, but my brain works in funny ways. So, having read this section, I’m still a little unclear on how one starts with X and the poset structure on X and, from only that, obtains the light cone structure. Are the tangent vectors defined as part of X or part of the poset structure?

    • CommentRowNumber44.
    • CommentAuthorIan_Durham
    • CommentTimeMay 26th 2010

    We do not say “Spacetime is a totally ordered set”. Only a “partially ordered set” :)

    Ah, OK, that explains a lot.

    In terms of terminology, I’m used to three notions of “time:” coordinate time, proper time, and spacetime intervals. I will admit that I fall back on the colloquial notion of “future” as specifically referring to coordinate time. But as long as I know you take it to imply a reference to the lightcones, I’m OK with that.

    I’m still a little uncertain about constructing the lightcone from the poset (see comment above).

    • CommentRowNumber45.
    • CommentAuthorEric
    • CommentTimeMay 26th 2010

    @Ian: Since we posted within 4 minutes of each other, I hope my 4 minute-earlier-comment helps answer your question. We must have been outside each others lightcones :)

    • CommentRowNumber46.
    • CommentAuthorEric
    • CommentTimeMay 26th 2010
    • (edited May 26th 2010)

    I’m still a little uncertain about constructing the lightcone from the poset (see comment above).

    FutureLightcone(x)={yX|x<y}FutureLightcone(x) = \{y\in X | x \lt y\} PastLightcone(x)={yX|y<x}PastLightcone(x) = \{y\in X | y \lt x\}

    Edit: Once you see it, you will feel cheated because it is so obvious :) But the obviousness is good news because we can now think of “lightcone structure” and “poset” as (almost) synonymous, i.e. given one you can determine the other.

    Edit^2: And posets (or preorders really) are nice because they form a particularly nice kind of category. The symbol x<yx\lt y means there is a morphism xyx\to y and for any two x,yx,y, there is at most one such morphism :)

    • CommentRowNumber47.
    • CommentAuthorIan_Durham
    • CommentTimeMay 26th 2010

    Right, but how would you be able to distinguish a poset that describes a Newtonian version of time from one that describes an Einsteinian one? Or do we just assume it is Einsteinian, i.e. we’re assuming everything is either proper time or spacetime intervals?

    • CommentRowNumber48.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeMay 26th 2010

    First, the words “in the future” are synonymous with “in the future lightcone”.

    Only on Minkowski space. On a general spacetime it means: connected by a future-directed path.

    • CommentRowNumber49.
    • CommentAuthorIan_Durham
    • CommentTimeMay 26th 2010
    • (edited May 26th 2010)

    Let me clarify my previous comment since it might seem a bit muddled.

    So, let’s take the simple Minkowski metric in 4-D spacetime,

    Δs 2=Δt 2Δd 2\Delta s^{2} = \Delta t^{2} - \Delta d^{2} (where I’ve chosen the +,-,-,- signature over the -,+,+,+ one)

    where dd represents the spatial separation of two events. Call tt the coordinate time and ss the spacetime interval. We can also think of tt as corresponding to ‘Newtonian’ time. ss is invariant under Lorentz transformations while tt is not. When Δs 20\Delta s^{2} \ge 0, the events separated by Δs\Delta s are causally connected, i.e. they are either timelike or lightlike separated.

    How does a simple poset capture the detail in that structure? And couldn’t you develop a poset that only described tt? Then how could you distinguish between the poset describing ss and the poset describing tt? And how could you recover the notion that two events might not be causally connected to one another, but both could be causally connected to some third event?

    Does anyone see what I mean? I’m trying really hard! :/

    • CommentRowNumber50.
    • CommentAuthorEric
    • CommentTimeMay 26th 2010
    • (edited May 26th 2010)

    Right, but how would you be able to distinguish a poset that describes a Newtonian version of time from one that describes an Einsteinian one? Or do we just assume it is Einsteinian, i.e. we’re assuming everything is either proper time or spacetime intervals?

    Good question :) I don’t know :)

    The difference between Newtonian version and Lorentzian (don’t give Einstein credit for everything :)) version has to do with the speed of light. Newtonian is the limit of Lorentzian as cc\to\infty, so your question could be rephrased as “What determines the speed of light?”

    I’m sure the answer lays in some of the references Bombelli points to, but I’m sure it has something to do with the follow…

    Given a set PP and a partial order <\lt on PP, then any element pPp\in P partions PP into three pieces

    1. Future(p)={pP|p<p}Future(p) = \{p'\in P | p\lt p'\}
    2. Past(p)={pP|p<p}Past(p) = \{p'\in P | p'\lt p\}
    3. Unrelated(p)={pFuture(p)&pPast(p)}Unrelated(p) = \{p'\notin Future(p)\;\&\; p'\notin Past(p)\}

    The speed of light must be related to the relative size of Unrelated(p)Unrelated(p). In the Newtonian case, Unrelated(p)Unrelated(p) is empty since the cone angle is 90 degrees (speed of light is infinite) and all points are ordered. In other words, a Newtonian spacetime is a totally ordered set. Given any two points in a Newtonian spacetime, you can always tell which is in the future of the other.

    For a finite speed of light, Unrelated(p)Unrelated(p) is not empty and we have a partially ordered set. As the speed of light decreases, the relative size of Unrelated(p)Unrelated(p) grows.

    • CommentRowNumber51.
    • CommentAuthorEric
    • CommentTimeMay 26th 2010
    • (edited May 26th 2010)

    First, the words “in the future” are synonymous with “in the future lightcone”.

    Only on Minkowski space. On a general spacetime it means: connected by a future-directed path.

    I think this is another semantic issue and I could be the culprit :)

    The collection of all future-directed paths, is what I meant by future lightcone. It is not a Minkowski cone, but should still be cone-shaped. If not, I have no problem with sticking to “connected by a future-directed path”, but I thought this was precisely how you’d define a lightcone in a general Lorentzian manifold, but I admit my use of terminology may not be standard either.

    • CommentRowNumber52.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeMay 26th 2010
    • (edited May 26th 2010)

    How does a simple poset capture the detail in that structure?

    Do you see how knowledge of the light-like vectors together with the volume element at any point determines a Lorentzian metric at that point?

    When you see that, the remaining step is to extract from the causal structure alone the light-like vectors. But the collection of all points in the future of a given point is the light-cone. So all you need to do is find the tangents to it, at your given point.

    • CommentRowNumber53.
    • CommentAuthorIan_Durham
    • CommentTimeMay 26th 2010

    Ah, ok, it is much clearer now. Eric’s description makes complete sense. To be honest (just being honest here!), if I had only Urs’ most recent comment to work from, I would still have wanted to better understand the statement “[b]ut the collection of all points in the future of a given point is the light-cone,” but I think Eric’s description clears it up.

    So, in short, I think I get it now. Many thanks to everyone for your patience.

    • CommentRowNumber54.
    • CommentAuthorEric
    • CommentTimeMay 26th 2010

    Cool :)

    Now ponder the far reaching implications… :)

    • CommentRowNumber55.
    • CommentAuthorIan_Durham
    • CommentTimeMay 26th 2010

    @Eric: By the way, you said you didn’t know the answer to my question about Newtonian versus Lorentzian time, but in the exact same post I think you explained it quite well. So you really did know. :-)

    • CommentRowNumber56.
    • CommentAuthorTim_van_Beek
    • CommentTimeMay 26th 2010

    Eric said:

    The collection of all future-directed paths, is what I meant by future lightcone.

    You may use chronological or causal future as defined now on smooth Lorentzian space.

    It is not a Minkowski cone, but should still be cone-shaped.

    I don’t know what “cone-shaped” means for a general manifold, but there is a “niceness” theorem about the boundary of the chronological future of a point that I also added, below the definition of chronological future.

    The speed of light must be related to the relative size of Unrelated(p).

    Just an addendum: For spacetime to be locally Lorentzian the important fact is that there is an upper bound on the velocity of signal propagation at all. How “fast” that is or if it is a maximum or only a supremum is secondary (i.e. there need not be a physical process that actually propagates with that speed, like light in the vacuum does in general relativity). But if you change the poset structure you will probably get different Lorentzian manifolds associated to it, I would guess.

    • CommentRowNumber57.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeMay 26th 2010

    but there is a “niceness” theorem about the boundary of the chronological future of a point that I also added, below the definition of chronological future.

    Thanks, Tim! Very useful.

    • CommentRowNumber58.
    • CommentAuthorIan_Durham
    • CommentTimeMay 26th 2010
    OK, now I have a question about Isham's sheaf-theoretic interpretation of the Kochen-Specker theorem and I think it may serve as a "litmus test" of my understanding of the "physical interpretation" (application?) of topos theory here.

    So Isham shows that KS is equivalent to the statement that the spectral presheaf has no global elements. But then the paper ends. But based on his "truth-object option" on page 16, since power [objects, sets, anything] always have a global element, the "power spectral presheaf" (what would you call it?) should have a global element. According to his option 1 on page 16 (if I'm reading it right), then, there's a relation between the existence of global elements due to power sets and classical physical states.

    Question: Can we thus recover the classical world from the quantum world (or at least one part of it) by taking the "power spectral presheaf" which makes KS inapplicable?

    I hope that makes sense (and I hope someone else has read that far in the paper).