Not signed in (Sign In)

Not signed in

Want to take part in these discussions? Sign in if you have an account, or apply for one below

  • Sign in using OpenID

Site Tag Cloud

2-category 2-category-theory abelian-categories adjoint algebra algebraic algebraic-geometry algebraic-topology analysis analytic-geometry arithmetic arithmetic-geometry book bundles calculus categorical categories category category-theory chern-weil-theory cohesion cohesive-homotopy-type-theory cohomology colimits combinatorics complex complex-geometry computable-mathematics computer-science constructive cosmology deformation-theory descent diagrams differential differential-cohomology differential-equations differential-geometry digraphs duality elliptic-cohomology enriched fibration foundation foundations functional-analysis functor gauge-theory gebra geometric-quantization geometry graph graphs gravity grothendieck group group-theory harmonic-analysis higher higher-algebra higher-category-theory higher-differential-geometry higher-geometry higher-lie-theory higher-topos-theory homological homological-algebra homotopy homotopy-theory homotopy-type-theory index-theory integration integration-theory internal-categories k-theory lie-theory limits linear linear-algebra locale localization logic mathematics measure measure-theory modal modal-logic model model-category-theory monad monads monoidal monoidal-category-theory morphism motives motivic-cohomology nlab noncommutative noncommutative-geometry number-theory of operads operator operator-algebra order-theory pages pasting philosophy physics pro-object probability probability-theory quantization quantum quantum-field quantum-field-theory quantum-mechanics quantum-physics quantum-theory question representation representation-theory riemannian-geometry scheme schemes set set-theory sheaf simplicial space spin-geometry stable-homotopy-theory stack string string-theory superalgebra supergeometry svg symplectic-geometry synthetic-differential-geometry terminology theory topology topos topos-theory tqft type type-theory universal variational-calculus

Vanilla 1.1.10 is a product of Lussumo. More Information: Documentation, Community Support.

Welcome to nForum
If you want to take part in these discussions either sign in now (if you have an account), apply for one now (if you don't).
    • CommentRowNumber1.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeJul 22nd 2010

    There is IMO some confusion in the article exterior algebra, in the examples section “Over a super vector space”.

    Very generally, for a cocomplete symmetric monoidal closed VectVect-enriched category VV (these hypotheses can be weakened), we have two distinct constructions:

    (1) The symmetric algebra S(X)= n0X n/S nS(X) = \sum_{n \geq 0} X^{\otimes n}/S_n. This is the free commutative monoid on XX.

    (2) The exterior algebra ΛX= n0sgn(n) S nX n\Lambda X = \sum_{n \geq 0} sgn(n) \otimes_{S_n} X^{\otimes n}.

    These are different things, although there are of course connections between them. Particularly, for V=V = super vector spaces, we have the fundamental relation

    (ΛV)[1]S(V[1])(\Lambda V)[1] \cong S(V[1])

    where the [1][1] indicates the degree 1 shift (mod 2).

    Now, in the article, there is the following statement

    For VV a super vector space, the exterior algebra ΛV\Lambda V is often called the Grassmann algebra over VV. This is the ΛV\Lambda V or V\wedge^\bullet V is the free graded commutative superalgebra on VV.

    This says in other words that the exterior algebra ΛX\Lambda X is the free graded commutative algebra on XX. Which is wrong, or at least confused; to make a correct statement, one has to take into account the two degree 1 shifts: ΛX=S(X[1])[1]\Lambda X = S(X[1])[-1]. Matters become potentially even more confusing when the grading is not just mod 2, but graded by \mathbb{Z} (or \mathbb{N}).

    This relates to what I was trying to say yesterday about the definition of CE-algebra. You might say that the underlying graded object is a Grassmann algebra on 𝔤\mathfrak{g}, but in order to do that you have to undergo contortions. You can’t really say Grassmann algebra on 𝔤\mathfrak{g} if 𝔤\mathfrak{g} is regarded as concentrated in degree 0, because strictly speaking that Grassmann algebra = exterior algebra would again be concentrated in degree 0, according to the definition given in exterior algebra. Nor can you really say Grassmann algebra = exterior algebra on the degree 1 shift 𝔤[1]\mathfrak{g}[1], because by what was said above, the exterior algebra construction on that gives, in degree nn, the object of commuting monomials 𝔤 n/S n\mathfrak{g}^{\otimes n}/S_n!

    No, what you really want to say in order to be coherent is that we are taking the free graded commutative algebra on 𝔤[1]\mathfrak{g}[1] (and then remark that the degree nn component is Λ n𝔤\Lambda^n \mathfrak{g}). This is a conceptually simpler way of thinking about it IMO, because one can invoke some general abstract nonsense, to the effect that in any (cocomplete symmetric monoidal closed VectVect-enriched) VV, if S(X)S(X) is the free commutative monoid, then any map XS(X)X \to S(X) extends uniquely to a derivation S(X)S(X)S(X) \to S(X) (and similarly for the free monoid T(X)T(X) in place of S(X)S(X)). This is what I was getting at when I had written yesterday at Chevalley-Eilenberg algebra.

    • CommentRowNumber2.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeJul 22nd 2010
    • (edited Jul 22nd 2010)

    The degree shift conventions are an endless source of amusement in this business.

    This says in other words that the exterior algebra X\wedge X is the free graded commutative algebra on XX. Which is wrong,

    To me the symbol \wedge means shift up by one and apply SymSym.

    That fits nicely with the ordinary convention that people think of a Lie algebra as having a vector space in degree 0 underlying it. Then 𝔤 *\wedge^\bullet \mathfrak{g}^* is the correct thing that underlies the CE-algebra.

    And it is Sym(𝔤 *[1])Sym(\mathfrak{g}^*[1]) not Sym(𝔤 *[1])[1]Sym(\mathfrak{g}^*[1])[-1]. Why do you mean to shift down again? We want

    𝔤 *=k𝔤 *𝔤 *𝔤 * \wedge^\bullet \mathfrak{g}^* = k \oplus \mathfrak{g}^* \oplus \mathfrak{g}^* \wedge \mathfrak{g}^* \oplus \cdots

    with the nnth power in degree nn.

    This is arranged to nicely fit with the common (though unfortunately not universal) convention that people like to take their Lie nn-algebra to be concentrated in degree 0, -1, -2, … -(n1)(n-1). Then 𝔤 *\mathfrak{g}^* is concentrated in degree 0 to (n1)(n-1). And 𝔤 *\wedge^\bullet \mathfrak{g}^* is the correct algebra underlying its CE-algebra.

    • CommentRowNumber3.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeJul 22nd 2010

    A reference example that is good to remain consistent with is the archetypical one: the de Rham complex on XX

    This is written

    C (X) Γ(T *X) \wedge^\bullet_{C^\infty(X)} \Gamma(T^* X)

    and has to come out as

    =Sym C (X)(Γ(T *X)[1]) \cdots = Sym_{C^\infty(X)}( \Gamma(T^* X)[1])

    (in fact many/most people would write [1][-1] instead of [1][1] for the up-shift.)

    • CommentRowNumber4.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeJul 22nd 2010

    Urs, I think maybe you missed my point (probably, paradoxically, because all this is obvious to you anyway).

    In the article Chevalley-Eilenberg algebra, the term “Grassmann algebra” is hyperlinked to exterior algebra. The reader who follows this link is then given the definition of exterior algebra which says essentially

    Λ(X)= n0sgn(n) S nX n\Lambda(X) = \sum_{n \geq 0} sgn(n) \otimes_{S_n} X^{\otimes n}

    Unless I missed something, it does not say in the definition section

    the symbol \wedge means shift up by one and apply SymSym.

    which, exactly, was my whole point: the Grassmann algebra as graded algebra is this. (And that’s what we should be saying, but it’s said very confusingly at exterior algebra. Look again at the quotation again in my first comment.) It is the result of applying the symmetric algebra functor to an appropriately graded object. It is not the result of applying the exterior algebra functor, as defined above, to some object in the symmetric monoidal category of graded vector spaces. For if you apply that definition of exterior algebra literally to an object in degree 0, you still get an object in degree 0. If you apply the exterior algebra functor to an object in degree 1, you get instead the symmetric algebra with its standard grading.

    See my point?

    You understand this perfectly well, but the neophyte attempting to follow links could quite easily become very confused, because the statements in the article are garbled IMO.

    And it is Sym(𝔤 *[1])Sym(\mathfrak{g}^*[1]) not Sym(𝔤 *[1])[1]Sym(\mathfrak{g}^*[1])[-1]. Why do you mean to shift down again?

    Oh, sorry; you’re right. There was a reason I did that: you do that if you want the super (or graded) Grassmann algebra to be a monad on super (or graded) vector spaces (where morphisms are by definition degree 0 maps). The way I view it is like this: we are conjugating the symmetric algebra monad by the degree 1 (mod 2) shift functor to get another monad. You don’t get a monad if you just shift and apply SymSym, because then you’ve shifted degrees (e.g., the unit of the “monad” would be a degree 1 map).

    • CommentRowNumber5.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeJul 22nd 2010

    Okay, here is an attempt to clarify the CE-entry locally, first: i added a section Grading conventions

    • CommentRowNumber6.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeJul 22nd 2010

    Excellent; thanks Urs! Looks good.

    • CommentRowNumber7.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeJul 22nd 2010

    All right, thanks for pushing me to improve this CE entry (and fill it with content in the first place).

    • CommentRowNumber8.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeJul 22nd 2010

    I ought to state my feeling that CE-algebra fits in a general family of cobar constructions; I’m not sure how much this has been brought out at the Lab (maybe under L L_\infty-algebra?). This sort of thing has been on my mind lately. I am returning to thinking about bar and cobar constructions for operads, Koszul duality for quadratic operads, cyclic operads, and the like, where there are quite a few parallels between the theory of operads and the theory of algebras.

    But I also want to get back to understanding your theory of universal connections on classifying bundles.

    I may have asked you this before, but can one use such a universal connection to construct an explicit homotopy inverse to the canonical map GΩBGG \to \Omega B G for GG a Lie group? (We know on general grounds that the map is a weak homotopy equivalence, hence a homotopy equivalence, but it would be nice to have an explicit homotopy inverse.)

    • CommentRowNumber9.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeJul 23rd 2010
    • (edited Jul 23rd 2010)

    I may have asked you this before, but can one use such a universal connection to construct an explicit homotopy inverse to the canonical map

    It’s right, you asked me that before. The thing here is that this universal connection that i am talking about is constructed in a sheaf topos, not in TopTop or DiffDiff. So it has the familiar tautological flavor to it and does not seem to readily yield explicit topological constructions such as you are after. At least not without further thinking.

    In fact, if you look at the consstruction, it boils down to something very tautological indeed. The interesting point (as far as I see it) is not so much that it exists, but how it fits into a grander scheme of things.

    You see, what I am currently still trying to work out better is this: I have a model for what a general \infty-connection on a general principal \infty-bundle is. I know from a bunch of examples that this model is correct. But only for parts of this model do I have a first-principles abstract nonsense derivation that explains why this must be the right answer.

    What I do have fully clarified, I think, is the case where the coefficient object BG\mathbf{B}G is once deloopable. In this “semi-abelian” case there is, I can show, a general-abstract theory for obstruction classes to extending BG\mathbf{B}G-cocycles to flat differential cocycles and when one turns the crank on this nice bit ob abstract (,1)(\infty,1)-category theory, out drops semi-abelian differential cohomology, such as Deligne cohomology, describing abelian nn-gerbes with connection.

    Okay, so that much is a done deal. Now the next observation is this: I take the explicit model (read: model category-model) that I proved present the above-mentioned abstract theory for semi-abelian differential cohomology in terms of 1-categorical data. Looking at this model with the eyes of the articles I wrote with Stasheff and Sati, there is an evident generalization of the model to the fully general non-necessarily semi-abelian case. And looking at examples, this evident generalization does the right thing.

    Okay. So back then I was happy with this. But today I can’t accept this. I have now a model of which I don’t fully know what it models. There must be a general-abstract mechanism at work in the background, which is a tad more complicated than that for the semi-abelian case wich I do understand.

    So I am trying to find this general abstract mechanism. The stuff that wrote about universal connections on principal 1-bundles is something I came up with in this process. It is an observation of how the simple familiar notion of a connection on a principal bundle may be reformulated as a bunch of almost-fully-abstract nonsense.

    For instance, I finally figured out the fully abstract way to say “Maurer-Cartan form”. I mean, in such generality that it works in any (,1)(\infty,1)-topos. I don’t even need to have a notion of “differential form” to say this. But it reduces to that case in the (,1)(\infty,1)-topos of \infty-Lie groupoids.

    When I finally had this, I saw that this provides a step in understanding the abstract procedure behind my model for nonabelian differential cohomology. In a pretty precise sense, this goes two thirds of the way! The remaining third is that open question which I tried to ask for help about in another thread.

    What I wrote about the universal connection on a 1-bundle in an \infty-stack topos is just a proof-of-principle sort of that shows how this abstract machinery really does reproduce the familiar notions. The construciton does not really say anything new about these familiar notions, and likely does not help much with questions such as you were asking. What it does accomplish, for me, is to point the way for generalizing this to differential cohomology beyond the familiar notions.