Not signed in (Sign In)

Not signed in

Want to take part in these discussions? Sign in if you have an account, or apply for one below

  • Sign in using OpenID

Site Tag Cloud

2-category 2-category-theory abelian-categories adjoint algebra algebraic algebraic-geometry algebraic-topology analysis analytic-geometry arithmetic arithmetic-geometry book bundles calculus categorical categories category category-theory chern-weil-theory cohesion cohesive-homotopy-type-theory cohomology colimits combinatorics complex complex-geometry computable-mathematics computer-science constructive cosmology deformation-theory descent diagrams differential differential-cohomology differential-equations differential-geometry digraphs duality elliptic-cohomology enriched fibration foundation foundations functional-analysis functor gauge-theory gebra geometric-quantization geometry graph graphs gravity grothendieck group group-theory harmonic-analysis higher higher-algebra higher-category-theory higher-differential-geometry higher-geometry higher-lie-theory higher-topos-theory homological homological-algebra homotopy homotopy-theory homotopy-type-theory index-theory integration integration-theory k-theory lie-theory limits linear linear-algebra locale localization logic mathematics measure-theory modal modal-logic model model-category-theory monad monads monoidal monoidal-category-theory morphism motives motivic-cohomology nforum nlab noncommutative noncommutative-geometry number-theory of operads operator operator-algebra order-theory pages pasting philosophy physics pro-object probability probability-theory quantization quantum quantum-field quantum-field-theory quantum-mechanics quantum-physics quantum-theory question representation representation-theory riemannian-geometry scheme schemes set set-theory sheaf sheaves simplicial space spin-geometry stable-homotopy-theory stack string string-theory superalgebra supergeometry svg symplectic-geometry synthetic-differential-geometry terminology theory topology topos topos-theory tqft type type-theory universal variational-calculus

Vanilla 1.1.10 is a product of Lussumo. More Information: Documentation, Community Support.

Welcome to nForum
If you want to take part in these discussions either sign in now (if you have an account), apply for one now (if you don't).
    • CommentRowNumber1.
    • CommentAuthorHarry Gindi
    • CommentTimeAug 7th 2010

    Before asking this question, we must recall some notions:


    Fix an excellent (therefore symmetric monoidal closed, combinatorial, and all monomorphisms are cofibrations (there’s more, but we don’t need it now)) model category SS (note: SS behaves in almost every way like the category of simplicial sets with the cartesian monoidal structure. If you’re not familiar with the definition of excellent, pretend that SS is the category of simplicial sets).

    We say that an SS-enriched category CC is AA-filtered, or equipped with an AA-filtration, for a fixed poset AA if there exists a function r:Ob(C)Ar:Ob(C)\to A such that if r(X)r(Y)r(X)\nleq r(Y), Map C(X,Y)=Map_C(X,Y)=\emptyset where \emptyset is the initial object of SS.

    Any AA-filtered SS-category gives rise to a functor ACat SA\to Cat_S as follows: Let C aC_{\leq a} be the full subcategory of CC spanned by the set of objects XX such that r(X)ar(X)\leq a. This gives a filtered diagram of subcategories of CC, given by the assignment aC aa\mapsto C_{\leq a} (considered as a functor ACat SA\to Cat_S).


    Recall that the model structure on Cat SCat_S is combinatorial (and therefore cofibrantly generated and given as follows:

    Recall that there exists a small set of generators for Cof(S). Fix such a set of generators and call it kk.

    Define [1] ACat S[1]_A\in Cat_S for any object ASA\in S as the category with two objects a,ba,b such that Map(a,a)=1 SMap(a,a)=1_S, Map(b,b)=1 SMap(b,b)=1_S, Map(a,b)=AMap(a,b)=A, and Map(b,a)=Map(b,a)=\emptyset. Define [0][0] to be the SS-category with one object xx such that Map(x,x)=Map(x,x)=\emptyset.

    Define the set QQ to be the set containing the unique map Cat S[0]\emptyset_{Cat_S}\to [0], and all of the induced maps [1] A[1] B[1]_A\to [1]_B induced by generating cofibrations (AB)k(A\to B)\in k

    Then we define:

    Cof(Cat_S)=llp(rlp(Q))

    We define the class of weak equivalences as follows:

    A weak equivalence of SS-categories is an SS-enriched functor f:CDf:C\to D such that:

    • Map C(X,Y)Map D(fX,fY)Map_C(X,Y)\to Map_D(fX,fY) is a weak equivalence in SS

    • For every YDY\in D, there exists an object XCX\in C such that YY is SS-equivalent to F(X)F(X) (homotopy essential surjectivity)

    It’s well-known that these two classes define a model structure on Cat SCat_S.

    (Recall that a morphism gg of an SS-enriched category CC is called an equivalence if the corresponding map hghg in the Ho(S)-enriched category hChC is an isomorphism.)


    Let CC be a model category. Recall that a natural transformation in a diagram category C DC^D is called a weak equivalence (resp. projective fibration) if it is a weak-equivalence object-by-object (resp. a fibration object-by-object). The projective cofibrations are precisely those natural transformations with the left lifting property with respect to all natural transformations that are both fibrations and weak equivalences. If CC is left-proper combinatorial and DD is small, then C DC^D with the projective model structure is likewise.


    HTT Lemma A.3.5.9 states:

    For AA a poset and S an excellent model category, any AA-filtered SS-enriched category CC admits an SS-enriched functor f:CCf:C'\to C such that:

    • f is bijective on objects, and the morphisms Map C(X,Y)Map C(fX,fY)Map_{C'}(X,Y)\to Map_C(fX,fY) are trivial fibrations,
    • CC' is endowed with an induced AA-filtration by composition rfr\circ f,
    • the induced diagram aC aa\mapsto C'_{\leq a} is a projectively cofibrant object of the model category Cat S ACat_S^A

    This is given without proof, but there is a hint that one should use the small object argument. First of all, to show this, do we need to use the SS-enriched version of the small object argument? If so, could someone give me a reference that states and proves this form of the small object argument (see the nLab page for an informal description, but no actual statement or proof)?

    If not, could someone break down exactly how to prove this?

    • CommentRowNumber2.
    • CommentAuthorHarry Gindi
    • CommentTimeAug 8th 2010
    • (edited Aug 8th 2010)

    Nevermind, I got a response from Lurie by e-mail. I guess I’ll expand it out and write this up on an nLab page, since I went to the trouble of writing all of the background up! =)