Want to take part in these discussions? Sign in if you have an account, or apply for one below
Vanilla 1.1.10 is a product of Lussumo. More Information: Documentation, Community Support.
1 to 29 of 29
Here is where I’ll blog my redaing of Topological Quantum Field Theories from Compact Lie Groups
day 1. quickly read the intro and gone directly to section1. main statement there is proposition 1.2, identifying with the group of abelian characters . in nLab we have a nice understanding of this identification as follows: the set of abelian characters is the set of cocycles , and the above identification follows by the long fibration sequence of oo-Lie groupoids
The description of the tqft associated with is given explicitely. Apparently it can be interpreted as follows: the vector space associated to a point is the space of sections of the line bundle on the groupoid induced by the cocycle (this space of sections will be - or -dimensional depending whether is the trivial cocycle or not). The complex number associated to is the dimension of this vector space. This can be seen as the integral over of the morphism induced by .
That is related this way to the space of maps from to and to the cocycle seems to be what is really crucial here. Yet in section 1 no deep reason for this being “the right answer” is given at this level and it is only remarked that the above described interpretation of is possible.
Thanks, for starting this, Domenico.
The complex number associated to is the dimension of this vector space. This can be seen as the integral over of the morphism induced by .
We said the following before elsewhere, but let’s recall it:
if we think of vector spaces and linear algebra along the lines of integral transforms on sheaves, then the morphism
is the path integral over the action, when regarded as an object in
where here: we have an -groupoid over and under groupoid-cardinality in this is the Haar measure-weighted path integral over .
Also just for the record, so that we get set up again for this discussion, this argument corresponds to theorem 6, page 16 of Simon Willerton’s article.
An analogous statement should holds for the space assigned to the point:
The identification goes via the -Grothendieck construction. So up to equivalence every element in the over -category is given by a fibration . This is like a flat bundle of -groupoids over : an -groupoid fiber over the point and then autoequivalences for each .
So the action functional again gives us a composite
and we ought to be able to interpret this under a cardinality operation as a vector space (by passing to (co)invariants).
So there should be this picture here: for we have
and we should be pull-pushing through this int the corresponding over -toposes.
Hi Urs,
thanks for joining this! :)
We said the following before elsewhere, but let’s recall it
yes, recalling that here is a very good idea, thanks.
and now… day 2 :)
I’ve skipped to Section 3 to see how the 0-1 tqft case is handled by the general theory. adapting for the beginning of Section 3, the starting point is the existence of the functor , which maps a manifold to the groupoid of principal -bundles oner ( is a finite group here). So this is nothing but the functor or, in the internal version .
Next, fixing to be the symmetric monoidal category involved, the classical theory is given by a lift of .Here, objects in are objects in , i.e., finite groupoids, with a morphism to ; morphisms are branes
In the case of a 0-1 tqft out of a cocycle the functor is defined by where the morphism to is induced by and by the standard representation of . This definition of therefore relies on the cobordism hypotesis in the version given by Theorem 2.1 in the paper: since is the trivial group, giving is the same thing that giving a fully dualizable object in .
This leaves it completely implicit what is on 1-manifolds, which is not completely satisfying. I’ll come back to this later.
Sill on the 0-1 tqft case. So far we have explicitly described only . The definition of forces to be the representation of dual of the one associated with . So, explicitely, , for . Then as a cobordism from to is the identity of as a representation of ; similarly, as a cobordism between and is the canonical pairing and as a cobordism between and is the copairing . Note that here we are using the fact that is the trivial 1-dimensional representation of , which is forced by the fact that has to be the unit in the symmetric monoidal category of representations of finite groupoids. Note that maps a 1-manifold with boundary to a morphism between functors to rather than to a functor from a groupoid to . This is obvious, since a 1-manifold is a 1-morphism in and so it has to be mapped to a 1-morphism in .
Next we come to . Since lifts , , this has has to be a functor . that is has to be a class function on . This is is agreement with the brane interpretation of morphisms: from the cospan we get the span of groupoids , and branes with this roof over are naturally identified with class functions on . and with the given data there is no better candidate for this class function than the cocycle itself, seen as a function . With this choice,
in accordance with the formula on page 4 of the paper.
Note that the fact that maps to a functor has a simple and natural interpretation: since is a cobordism from the empty manifold to itself, has to be a functor taking values in the space of morphisms of the unit of .
I’m not satisfied with the ad hoc definition of . I’d like this to be , induced by , but I’m presently unable to give a rigorous meaning to . Yet, I’m convinced precisely this is the key of the whole construction.
but I’m presently unable to give a rigorous meaning to .
The canonical interpretation would be as the functor category (or rather its core fr the purposes here) from the groupoid incarnation of to . That is the groupoid whose objects are linear endomorphisms on a vector space, and whose morphisms are conjugations by invertible linear maps.
What is important is, I think, that we regard as a pointed category, with point the ground field regarded as a vector space over itself. The component of on this component is (since ). So its 0-truncation is indeed .
Hi Urs,
the functor category interpretation works extremely well! and we do not need to regard as a pointed category nor to restrict to the core. Indeed, if is the functor induced by composed with the standard representation of , then the induced fnctor between functor categories maps the object to the object and the morphism to the morphism (where I left the conjugation explicit to have a form which is still valid for higher dimensional representations of ).
So this part is ok, and to finally land in we just need to take the trace, .
All right! :-)
we just need to take the trace
Hopefully that will be said more intrinsically. At least for the 1-dimensional case, this step is 0-truncation of .
Hopefully that will be said more intrinsically.
Yes, having a good intrinsic understanding of what is seems to be a crucial point here. I don’t clearly see this as the truncation morphism unless “the 1-dimensional case” refers to the dimension of the vector space in the object of .
Apart this, I was thinking that for a 1-dimensional manifold (with boundary), the functor category is a categorical verison of (a particular case of) the labelled diagrams appearing in Joyal-Street-Reshetikhin-Turaev graphical calculus for morphisms. So it seems that on the one hand we have a sort of “decorated cobordism” equipped with a natural morphism to given by the graphical calculus, and on the other we have the cocycle inducing . The composition of these is and pushing forward to the point gives the tqft .
So the crucial step seems to understand in arbitrary dimension.
The morphism should be completely natural and have the following interpretation: is the free symmetric monoidal category with duals generated by ; hence, for any symmetric monoidal category with duals and any functor , is induced a duality preserving symmetric monoidal functor extending .
This appears to be a simple repharsing of Joyal-Street-Reshetikhin-Turaev diagrammatics, and suggests the following general statement: is the adjoint of the inclusion symmetric monoidal -categories with duals-categories
Given an arbitrary symmetric monoidal -category , I expect that the full subcategory on fully dualizable objects is a symmetric monoidal -category with duals, so the conjectured adjuction above would in paticular give an equivalence between duality preserving symmetric monoidal functors and objects in , i.e., the cobordism hypothesis in its original formulation.
Coming back to the example, the above seems to say that a symmetric monoidal morphism is completely determined (or better its homotopy class is) by the morphism induced by the cocycle . Next the problem of pushing this forward to a symmetric monoidal morphism seems to be reduced to the problem of pushing forward along . This is a particular case of the problem of pushing forward a morphism along , where is any garoupioid, and this can in turn be conveniently expressed in terms of left or right Kan extensions. This precisely transates the limit or colimit formulation of in the paper.
according to this MO answer, the left adjoint point of view seems to be correct. I’ll be presently not working on the details of this, but rather will try to read the constructions in Freed-Hopkins-Lurie-Teleman in the light of it. The case sketched above seems to say that this point of view is promising.
I expect that the full subcategory on fully dualizable objects is a symmetric monoidal -category with duals
Yes, that’s part of claim 2.3.19 of Classification of TFTs . I have finally started an entry symmetric monoidal (infinity,n)-category and recorded that statement there.
Hi Domenico,
I had been distracted by some other things and seem to have lost you a bit. Could you say again what you said before about ? I understand that you say you want to think of this as denoting the free “with dual”ization of , but I am not sure if I see why and how.
(I do remember that before we discussed elsewhere that should be the free symmetric-monoidalization of in some sense.)
Also you write the cocycle induces . But by “” we used to denote the -category of cobordisms equipped with maps to . Is that still what you ,mean?
Sorry for not following, but if you could just restate in a paragraph what you are after now, that might help.
Hi Urs,
let me use two distinct notations here not to make things foggier than they deserve. On the one side we should have a left adjoint to the inclusion of symmetric monoidal -categories with duals into -categories. Let us denote this by . On the other side we have a notion of -decorated bordism, that is, precisely, -cobordism with maps to , something we could denote by or more explicitly .
The arguments in the final part of Classification of TQFTs seem to suggest an equivalence . Details of this are still unclear to me, except in the case where it is a familiar statement from Joyal-Street-Reshetikhin-Turaev. Assuming the statement is true, then by definition of adjointness we have, for any symmetric monoidal -category with duals , a natural morphism . What I’m saying is that (again at least in the case where I’ve gone through the details) this nicely gives the construction in TQFTs from compact Lie groups.
Namely, induces . Since is a symmetric monoidal category with duals (I’m assuming is denoting the category of finite dimensional vector spaces), then we have the natural symmetric monoidal duality preserving morphism induced by the universal property of , and so we end up with a symmetric monoidal morphism . Now to end up witha tqft we are left with the task of pushing this forward along . Here the idea is: consider the Kan extension of along , and apply to the homotopy commutative diagram you obtatin the hom-functor . This, together with the natural morphism gives the diagram
whose “lower profile” should be the seeked tqft.
edit: is the lower profile the Kan extension
?
the case seems to go straightforwardly along these lines: a cocylce induces a morphism , where is the 2-category whose objects are algebras and whose morphisms are bimodules (this 2-category is denoted in FHLT). The defining representation maps the unique object of to the algebra , the unique 1-morphism of to vector space (as a -bimodule), and the element (as a 2-morphism in ) to the element . the Kan extension of along is the twisted group algebra of (this is example 3.14 in FHLT).
Hi Domenico,
sorry to be slowing things down, but I have more questions about what precisely you are thinking of now. Of course I recognize plenty of ideas here, but to make progress I feel I need better grip on where you are thinking of precise statements and where you are sketching how the story ought to run.
let me use two distinct notations here not to make things foggier than they deserve. On the one side we should have a left adjoint to the inclusion of symmetric monoidal -categories with duals into -categories. Let us denote this by . On the other side we have a notion of -decorated bordism, that is, precisely, -cobordism with maps to ,
What kind of map from a cobordism to are you thinking of here? Do you still map the groupoid to ?
something we could denote by or more explicitly .
The latter notation has an evident interpretation as the -category of (symmetric monoidal) -functors (i.e. an extended d-TFT with values in ). But I don’t think that that’s what you mean. I’d think it takes a bit more discussion to say what one might mean here. But maybe I am missing something.
except in the case where it is a familiar statement from Joyal-Street-Reshetikhin-Turaev
There is a famous “Reshitikhin-Turaev construction” for and a modular tensor category. That’s not what you mean, though?
the case seems to go straightforwardly along these lines: a cocylce induces a morphism , where is the 2-category whose objects are algebras and whose morphisms are bimodules (this 2-category is denoted in FHLT). The defining representation maps the unique object of to the algebra , the unique 1-morphism of to vector space (as a -bimodule), and the element (as a 2-morphism in ) to the element . the Kan extension of along is the twisted group algebra of (this is example 3.14 in FHLT).
Yes, over a point, the quantization construction is a plain colimit. When extending this to all cobordisms, things tend to get trickier.
Let me see…
Hi Urs,
no need to apologize: I see what I’m writing here is really foggy. What I’m trying to fix is an essential version of the constructions in FHLT: my impression there is that in many occasions they describe some object coming out of nowhere as the "right" object, and only after they give a simple general recipe which would have produced that specific object. This is particularly evident in the case of the tensor category defined in section 4 of FHLT: the general argument of the paper suggest that should arise very simply as the colimit of the functor induced by the cocycle , and by the defining representation mapping the unique object of to the tensor category of finite dimensional vector spaces over . Yet, this seems not to be stated explicitely in the paper.
So, for how trivial it is, I’m now going to spend some time to convince myself that what I’ve just written is correct :)
What kind of map from a cobordism to are you thinking of here? Do you still map the groupoid to ?
Yes, probably that’s the correct way of looking at what I’m at the moment thinking in more naive terms: namely, I’m presently thinking in terms of functors from a triangulation of to . Extremely rough, as you see. I guess you are right and is the right object to be considered.
something we could denote by or more explicitly .
You are right, teh second notation is absolutely confusing. What I had in mind is the following: maps a triangulated manifold to the . So, adoping the point of view (which I’m conviced should be the correct one), this should be
at least as a first approximation.
There is a famous "Reshitikhin-Turaev construction" for and a modular tensor category. That’s not what you mean, though?
I mean the following: given an arbitrary category , one can consider the category whose objects are finite sequences of objects of (each one equipped with a sign), and whose morphisms are oriented links between these sequences, with strands decorated by morphisms in . Juxtaposition of links and the "obvious" braiding makes this a symmetric monoidal category, and if i’m not wrong this should be the free symmetric monoidal category generated by . I’m not sure of the source for this construction, but I think I’ve learned it from works of Joyal-Street and Reshetikhin-Turaev.
Yes, over a point, the quantization construction is a plain colimit. When extending this to all cobordisms, things tend to get trickier.
Absolutely. But I’m confident we can get to the point where tricks disappear and things become completely natural. Having a good understandng of what happens over the point is a good beginning..
this should be […]
Yes. This is along the lines indicated in the entry on Topological Quantum Field Theories from Compact Lie Groups:
we imagine that we have an -topos into which manifolds faithfully embed . Then for every object there ought to be an -functor
given by sending a manifold with boundaries to the span of -groupoids
If is cohesive and is of the form then we have .
Now, given a morphism (an “action functional”) there ought to be an -stack object which assigns an -category of quasicoherent sheaves of -modules, and a canonical representation . Then the composite ought to be the full action functional. And using this morphism there ought to be a lift of the above
to or the like.
And then quantization ought to be postcomposition with a canonical morphism
Hi Urs,
ok, so the functor associated with an object is what I’m calling , while the -stack object is what I’ve implicitly been denoting .
So the way I figure things is that a morphism induces a morphism ; next should have a natural lift to a functor taking values in , and this should be the crucial point of the whole construction. Then the composition of these two maps should give
This is simply restating what you have just written above, stressing attention on . I mean: it doesn’t really matter how do we get to (a way could be, e.g., via a cocycle as we did several times); what really matters is wahat we are able to do once we are on , i.e., how do we canonically endow the oo-groupoids with morphisms to .
Push-forward along ?
ok, so the functor associated with an object is what I’m calling ,
Okay, good.
while the -stack object is what I’ve implicitly been denoting .
All right, this is less important, as this is just notation for an object that is kind of obvious. The -notation is a bit more suggestive for an object in a -sheaf topos, but maybe that need not be our primary concern at the moment.
So the way I figure things is that a morphism induces a morphism ;
Hm, okay, I see. That’s a slight variant of saying that the description in terms of that lift. Let me think about it.
how do we canonically endow the oo-groupoids with morphisms to .
I think we should come back to that nice fact that \mathbf{H}(\Pi(\Sigma_d),\mathbf{B}^n U(1)) \simeq \mathbf{B}^{n-d}U(1)$.
This means that over we get the data suitable for a transformation between the data over
However, I am not yet sure how to organize this properly.
Domenico,
please remind me: had you worked out the relative version of the truncation formula that is needed for what I said in the above comment?
For an -dimensional monifold with boundary , do we know how to get the natural transformation as above?
Hi Urs,
yes and no: I had tried to think to that in terms of relative cohomology but was no able to get to a clean result.
What confuses me about the truncation formula is that it seems to be much more restrictive than one would expect the theory to be: e.g., for one is delaing with line bundles, whereas things seem to go through for arbitrary vector bundles. That’s why I’d try to think directly in terms of rather than in terms of .
The basic construction we need to understand, I think, is the following: given a flat vector bundle (or more in general a vector bundle equipped with a connection) on a space , taking traces of holonomy gives a section of the -bundle over the loop space , where is the trivial -bundle. Here we are hiddenly using the fact that the trace gives a natural brane
where the bottom arrows pick out the algebra object in .
we have been around this several times, already, but I still think we have not got into the real mening of this; and indeed we are not able to see clearly which is the natural higher dimensional generalization. or at least I am not :)
Hi Urs,
I’m thinking to what you wrote in #19 again. That’s extremely neat, let me rewrite it in my words to see if I got the point: we have classical theories and quantum theories . The quantization of a classical theory is dealt with in FHLT, and is the natural functor
The crucial question, then is: given any object in a suitable -topos , this gives an obvious funtor ; can this functor be lifted to a classical theory? how?
these lift I would call classical theories over . Each of these gives, in particular a functor , corresponding to . The probelm is how much does this functor tell us of the eventual classical theory over ?
Hey, wait, the answer is: fully dualizable object! Namely, is a symmetric monoidal -category, so by the cobordism hypotesis giving a classical field theory, i.e., a symmetric monoidal functor is the same thing as giving a fully dualizable object in , i.e. a suitable functor with an oo-groupoid. More precisely, the datum of is equivalent to the datum of
Now, composing with the forgetful morphism gives a functor which (trivially) is lifted by . If the functor is representable, then it is represented by , since . This would mean that lifts a functor of the form as in the posts above. On the other hand, making the fully dualizable object be the cornerstone of the construction makes the issue of the representability of an interesting but probably not crucial question.
So, coming back to the FHLT paper, I think we should ask ourselves the following questions:
a) does preserve full dualizable objects?
b) are the “obvious” functors induced by cocycles fully dualizable objects in ?
c) is the defining representation a fully dualizable objects in ?
d) if is a fully dualizable object in and is an -functor, is the composition a fully dualizable object in (i.e., does c) implies b)? )
re #23, you write:
What confuses me about the truncation formula is that it seems to be much more restrictive than one would expect the theory to be: e.g., for n=1 one is delaing with line bundles, whereas things seem to go through for arbitrary vector bundles.
Yes, true, but I would be willing to believe that the case plays a special role that justifies it having its tailor-made theorems. After all, the Lagrangians for -Chern-Simons theory that we are trying to figure out the extended quantization of always take values in . So I wouldn’t be shocked if that case has a good general abstract quantization story, while a more general case does not.
I think the truncation formula we have works too well to easily discard it. After all, it is a general abstract way of saying “the action is the integral over the Lagrangian”. That should not be light-heartedly be discrded! :-)
Concerning your other comments: ’ll think about it and come back to it a little later. Need to get something else done first.
the truncation formula we have works too well to easily discard it. After all, it is a general abstract way of saying “the action is the integral over the Lagrangian”. That should not be light-heartedly be discrded! :-)
a very good point! absolutely! :)
concerning #25, the answer to a) is: trivially true. indeed that is an immediate consequence of the cobordism hypothesis and of the fact is a symmetric monoidal functor.
concerning question b) in #25, the answer is yes at least for and . Indeed, by the cobordism hypothesis, the value assigned to the point is a fully dualizable object, and in FHLT, what the functor does on the point in the 1- and 2- dimensional case is said explicitely: it maps the point to the representation of induced by the cocycle . I think one should expect the answer to be yes regardless of the dimension.
1 to 29 of 29