Not signed in (Sign In)

Not signed in

Want to take part in these discussions? Sign in if you have an account, or apply for one below

  • Sign in using OpenID

Site Tag Cloud

2-category 2-category-theory abelian-categories adjoint algebra algebraic algebraic-geometry algebraic-topology analysis analytic-geometry arithmetic arithmetic-geometry book bundles calculus categorical categories category category-theory chern-weil-theory cohesion cohesive-homotopy-type-theory cohomology colimits combinatorics complex complex-geometry computable-mathematics computer-science constructive cosmology deformation-theory descent diagrams differential differential-cohomology differential-equations differential-geometry digraphs duality elliptic-cohomology enriched fibration foundation foundations functional-analysis functor gauge-theory gebra geometric-quantization geometry graph graphs gravity grothendieck group group-theory harmonic-analysis higher higher-algebra higher-category-theory higher-differential-geometry higher-geometry higher-lie-theory higher-topos-theory homological homological-algebra homotopy homotopy-theory homotopy-type-theory index-theory integration integration-theory internal-categories k-theory lie-theory limits linear linear-algebra locale localization logic mathematics measure measure-theory modal modal-logic model model-category-theory monad monads monoidal monoidal-category-theory morphism motives motivic-cohomology nlab noncommutative noncommutative-geometry number-theory of operads operator operator-algebra order-theory pages pasting philosophy physics pro-object probability probability-theory quantization quantum quantum-field quantum-field-theory quantum-mechanics quantum-physics quantum-theory question representation representation-theory riemannian-geometry scheme schemes set set-theory sheaf simplicial space spin-geometry stable-homotopy-theory stack string string-theory superalgebra supergeometry svg symplectic-geometry synthetic-differential-geometry terminology theory topology topos topos-theory tqft type type-theory universal variational-calculus

Vanilla 1.1.10 is a product of Lussumo. More Information: Documentation, Community Support.

Welcome to nForum
If you want to take part in these discussions either sign in now (if you have an account), apply for one now (if you don't).
    • CommentRowNumber1.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeOct 21st 2009

    I started a section

    dependence on the underlying site at model structure on simplicial presheaves.

    So far this quotes a result from Jardine's lectures and then looks a bit at an example.

    At that example I would really like to conclude that the Quillen adjunction discussed there is actually a Quillen equivalence. But I have to interrupt now to make a telephone call... :-)

    • CommentRowNumber2.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeOct 22nd 2009

    a supposed proof that indeed we have a Quillen equivalence

     SPSh(Diff)_{inj}^{loc} \stackrel{\leftarrow}{\to} SPsh(CartSp)_{inj}^{loc}

    is now

    here in that entry

    of course Diff and CartSp is just one specific example. In as far as the proof is correct, it will work for all such pairs, for instance Schemes vs AffineSchemes .

    But check if it is indeed correct.

    • CommentRowNumber3.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeOct 22nd 2009

    now also added a section good covers with a definition that I think is good and with a proposition that I think is true and useful.

    However, it seems at this point of the night I seem to be unable to write down precisely what in my head seems to be the obvious proof. I wrote down something there, but need to get back to it. Maybe I am wrong, but I am not convinced of that as yet ;-)

    • CommentRowNumber4.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeOct 22nd 2009

    I think I got it right now.

    • CommentRowNumber5.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeOct 22nd 2009

    Danny Stevenson kindly wrote in to say that the fact in question

    (that every simplicial presheaf that is degreewise a coproduct of representables is cofibrant in alll these model structures)

    should be true and should be stated somewhere in Dan Dugger's work.

    He indicates a proof which sounds very much along the lines of the proof that I did give.

    So I regard this as settled for the time being, removed the green query boxes and just left in an indented remark that for the time being the proof is one I dreamed up which still deserves checking.

    • CommentRowNumber6.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeOct 22nd 2009

    renamed the section in question fibrant and cofibrant objects and expanded further.

    meanwhile Danny Stevenson writes in and points out various even stroger statements from the literature. Will try to include them after lunch...

    • CommentRowNumber7.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeMay 1st 2023
    • (edited May 1st 2023)

    just a vague thought:

    Is there a non-trivial class of small categories (of posets?) such that for any C 1C_1 and C 2C_2 in the class, the functor of pullback along (i.e. precomposition with) their product projections C 1×C 2C 1C_1 \times C_2 \to C_1 happens to be a left Quillen functor for the projective model structures on simplicial presheaves over these categories?

    [edit: I’d like these categories not to have a terminal object, in general…]

    • CommentRowNumber8.
    • CommentAuthorDmitri Pavlov
    • CommentTimeMay 1st 2023

    happens to be a left Quillen functor for the projective model structures on simplicial presheaves over these categories?

    This is true if and only if the left adjoint functor sends representable presheaves to projectively cofibrant objects. In our case, an object c_1∈C_1 is sent to the presheaf (d_1,d_2)↦C_1(d_1,c_1).

    Therefore, the latter presheaf has to be a retract of a coproduct of representables. This is true if C_2 has a terminal object, since in this case the resulting presheaf is representable by (c_1,1). Otherwise it is easy to construct examples when it’s false, so the answer depends on C_2.

    • CommentRowNumber9.
    • CommentAuthorGuest
    • CommentTimeMay 2nd 2023

    Thanks for the comments.

    I came to wonder about this in thinking about how to get the naive formula for an external tensor product to yield a derivable functor on an integral model structure. In some natural contexts I can see that it behaves like a left Quillen functor on an ambient integral model structure except that (or if only) the initial operation of pullback of either factor to the cartesian product of their bases spaces is or were left Quillen wrt the projective model strcuture.

    But this fails badly over sites of simplicial groupoids, since here cofibrancy essentially means free actions of the simplicial Kan loop group, and the partially trivial actions obtained by pullback along projections are as far from this as possible. In view of this, last night, I naively came to wonder whether if I’d pull a Thomason-trick and removed all manifest automorphisms by passing to posetal models of homotopy types I could get around this problem. But now I see that this is hopeless.

    As another solution to the problem I guess one could pick a “universe” of simplicial group {𝒢 i} iI\{\mathcal{G}_i\}_{i \in I} that one cares about, then blow up the point space to iIW¯W𝒢 i\underset{i \in I}{\prod} \overline{W} W\mathcal{G}_i (using here that W𝒢W\mathcal{G} has itself group structure) and blow up any connected homotopy type 𝒳W¯𝒢 i 0\mathcal{X} \simeq \overline{W}\mathcal{G}_{i_0} that one cares about to 𝒳×ii 0W¯W𝒢 i\mathcal{X} \times \underset{i \neq i_0}{\prod} \overline{W} W\mathcal{G}_i, thought of as sliced over the blown-up point via the inclusion 𝒢 i 0W𝒢 i 0\mathcal{G}_{i_0} \to W\mathcal{G}_{i_0} (using that this is in fact a group homomorphism) and the identity on all the other factors.

    This way, every cofibrant object parameterized by the blow-up of 𝒳\mathcal{X} is now freely acted on by all (the W𝒢 iW\mathcal{G}_i and hence) the 𝒢 i\mathcal{G}_i in the universe. Moreover, the product over the blown-up point of the blow-up of 𝒳W𝒢 i 0\mathcal{X} \simeq W\mathcal{G}_{i_0} with another 𝒳W𝒢 i 0\mathcal{X}' \simeq W\mathcal{G}_{i'_0} is now such that pullback to it along either of the two projections amounts to restricting, in the left factor, say, W𝒢 i 0W\mathcal{G}_{i_0}-actions along the inclusions 𝒢 i 0W𝒢 i 0\mathcal{G}_{i_0} \to W\mathcal{G}_{i_0}, which does preserve cofibrancy.

    • CommentRowNumber10.
    • CommentAuthorDmitri Pavlov
    • CommentTimeMay 2nd 2023

    Re #9: But if your goal is to make the external tensor product into a left Quillen bifunctor, then it seems like it is true: the external tensor product XYX\boxtimes Y of representable sheaves is simply the representable sheaf of the pair, which is cofibrant even though the individual factors p 1 *Xp_1^* X and p 2 *Yp_2^*Y are not.

    • CommentRowNumber11.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeMay 2nd 2023

    Oh right, that is true. :-)