Not signed in (Sign In)

Not signed in

Want to take part in these discussions? Sign in if you have an account, or apply for one below

  • Sign in using OpenID

Site Tag Cloud

2-category 2-category-theory abelian-categories adjoint algebra algebraic algebraic-geometry algebraic-topology analysis analytic-geometry arithmetic arithmetic-geometry book bundles calculus categorical categories category category-theory chern-weil-theory cohesion cohesive-homotopy-type-theory cohomology colimits combinatorics complex complex-geometry computable-mathematics computer-science constructive cosmology deformation-theory descent diagrams differential differential-cohomology differential-equations differential-geometry digraphs duality elliptic-cohomology enriched fibration foundation foundations functional-analysis functor gauge-theory gebra geometric-quantization geometry graph graphs gravity grothendieck group group-theory harmonic-analysis higher higher-algebra higher-category-theory higher-differential-geometry higher-geometry higher-lie-theory higher-topos-theory homological homological-algebra homotopy homotopy-theory homotopy-type-theory index-theory integration integration-theory k-theory lie-theory limits linear linear-algebra locale localization logic mathematics measure-theory modal modal-logic model model-category-theory monad monads monoidal monoidal-category-theory morphism motives motivic-cohomology nforum nlab noncommutative noncommutative-geometry number-theory of operads operator operator-algebra order-theory pages pasting philosophy physics pro-object probability probability-theory quantization quantum quantum-field quantum-field-theory quantum-mechanics quantum-physics quantum-theory question representation representation-theory riemannian-geometry scheme schemes set set-theory sheaf sheaves simplicial space spin-geometry stable-homotopy-theory stack string string-theory superalgebra supergeometry svg symplectic-geometry synthetic-differential-geometry terminology theory topology topos topos-theory tqft type type-theory universal variational-calculus

Vanilla 1.1.10 is a product of Lussumo. More Information: Documentation, Community Support.

Welcome to nForum
If you want to take part in these discussions either sign in now (if you have an account), apply for one now (if you don't).
    • CommentRowNumber1.
    • CommentAuthorYaron
    • CommentTimeJan 6th 2011

    Todd, thanks for this interesting entry (colimits in categories of algebras)! I left a query box describing a possible simple proof for the last theorem using the adjoint lifting theorem (I hope there are no substantial errors).

    • CommentRowNumber2.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeJan 6th 2011

    Yaron, yes you’re right (and thanks). If you’d like to go in and add this in as the official first proof, I’d be delighted. (But please don’t erase the pedestrian proof I wrote. I’ll rework that so that it looks like we’re giving a very concrete and hands-on description of the left adjoint; I think readers should be aware that this is not just some abstract black box or adjoint functor nonsense, but a construction they’re already familiar with from ordinary commutative algebra and module theory.)

    • CommentRowNumber3.
    • CommentAuthorYaron
    • CommentTimeJan 6th 2011

    Thanks for the answer, Todd. I’ll happily do the change (though it will take some time, since I have to go now).

    And of course I will not delete the existing proof. Actually, I was so eager to make it clear that the short proof is just an addition, that I re-edited the page twice only to add the word “also” (it can also be proved by…)
    :)

    • CommentRowNumber4.
    • CommentAuthorYaron
    • CommentTimeJan 6th 2011

    Done.

    • CommentRowNumber5.
    • CommentAuthorTim Campion
    • CommentTimeJul 10th 2016

    I’m having difficulty understanding Lemma 1. If ii is a section for pp, I understand that pp is an absolute coequalizer of ip,1:UBUBip, 1: UB \overset{\to}{\to} UB, so that TpTp is a coequalizer for Tip,1,TUBTUBTip, 1, TUB \overset{\to}{\to} TUB. But I don’t understand how this implies that TpTp is a coequalizer for TUπ 1,TUπ 2:TUETUBTU\pi_1, TU\pi_2: TUE \overset{\to}{\to} TUB.

    Somewhat relatedly, I fixed a typo in Corollary 1.

    I find Corollary 1 to be surprising because there is a characterization of categories which are monadic over Set\mathsf{Set} (Thm 4.4.5 in the Handbook of Categorical Algebra vol. 2, also discussed by Vitale), and I don’t see anything in the characterization that obviously implies the existence of all coequalizers (although some coproducts are implied).

    • CommentRowNumber6.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeJul 10th 2016

    I meant a coequalizer of a split fork. Sorry.

    I am fairly sure that categories that are monadic over SetSet are cocomplete. This is probably in Manes’ book, and the result might be due to Linton.

    • CommentRowNumber7.
    • CommentAuthorMike Shulman
    • CommentTimeJul 10th 2016

    In fact, I believe that categories monadic over Set are not just cocomplete but total.

    • CommentRowNumber8.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeJul 10th 2016

    Indeed.

    • CommentRowNumber9.
    • CommentAuthorTim Campion
    • CommentTimeJul 10th 2016

    Okay, I think I understand now.

    1. pp is a coequalizer for (Uπ 1,Uπ 2)(U\pi_1,U\pi_2).
    2. Take a section ii for pp. Then pp is also an absolute coequalizer for (ip,1)(ip,1).
    3. So the monadic functor U:TAlgSetU: T-Alg \to Set creates this absolute coequalizer in TAlgT-Alg.
    4. If f:BXf: B \to X coequalizes (Uπ 1,Uπ 2)(U\pi_1,U\pi_2), then ff factors uniquely as f=f¯pf = \bar f p.
    5. It follows that ff coequalizes (ip,1)(ip,1). So f¯\bar f is an algebra homomorphism.

    The fact I wasn’t aware of is that if a functor creates one coequalizer, then it creates any other coequalizer with the same quotient. It’s weird to me, partly because I’m not sure how to generalize this fact to other indexing shapes.

    • CommentRowNumber10.
    • CommentAuthorTodd_Trimble
    • CommentTimeJul 10th 2016
    • (edited Jul 11th 2016)

    If you’re willing to settle for mere cocompleteness of Set TSet^T :-), then the crucial thing which might need spelling out in that article is that if π 1,π 2:EX×X\langle \pi_1, \pi_2 \rangle: E \hookrightarrow X \times X is an equivalence relation in SetSet and

    Eπ 2π 1XqYE \stackrel{\overset{\pi_1}{\longrightarrow}}{\underset{\pi_2}{\longrightarrow}} X \stackrel{q}{\to} Y

    is exact, then this fork splits. Proof: choose a section ss of qq. This gives a basepoint s(y)s(y) for each equivalence class yY=X/Ey \in Y = X/E. A splitting of the fork is given by ss together with XE:x(x,sq(x))EX \to E: x \mapsto (x, s q(x)) \in E. Of course, split forks are absolute coequalizers, so TT will preserve them.

    Clear now?

    • CommentRowNumber11.
    • CommentAuthorTim Campion
    • CommentTimeJul 10th 2016

    I thought I posted this a little while ago, but apparently it didn’t go up:

    It’s clear to me now, thanks. I’m surprised to learn that any equivalence relation in SetSet is already split, and hence absolute. I guess I should be familiar with this fact, since it explains why quotients by congruence relations in monadic categories are computed as in SetSet.

    Looking back, that’s exactly what it the article already said. I think what threw me was the part I “fixed”: it didn’t occur to me that the bracket notation in ip,1:BE\langle ip, 1 \rangle : B \to E could really denote a map into EE rather than B×BB \times B, so I misinterpreted it as meaning a pair of maps BBB \to B forming the “fork” part of a split fork. I’m not sure it could really be any clearer, though. The one change I would make would be to write UBUEUB \to UE instead of BEB \to E since these maps live downstairs.

    The funny thing is that the proof I gave doesn’t require kernel pairs to exist: it in fact shows that if CC has (reflexive) coequalizers whose quotient maps split, then C TC^T has (reflexive) coequalizers for any monad TT. I’m not sure how this slight increase in generality could be useful, though.

    • CommentRowNumber12.
    • CommentAuthorTim Campion
    • CommentTimeJul 11th 2016

    Never mind, my own proof doesn’t make sense.

    • CommentRowNumber13.
    • CommentAuthorvarkor
    • CommentTimeMar 21st 2023

    Rename “relative forgetful functor” to “algebraic functor”, which is the usual terminology.

    diff, v33, current

    • CommentRowNumber14.
    • CommentAuthorvarkor
    • CommentTimeMar 21st 2023

    Add a reference for creation of colimits.

    diff, v34, current