Want to take part in these discussions? Sign in if you have an account, or apply for one below
Vanilla 1.1.10 is a product of Lussumo. More Information: Documentation, Community Support.
at surjective geometric morphism I have spelled out in detail most of the proof of the various equivalent characterizations, and all of the proof of the statement that geometric surjections are comonadic.
Added to surjective geometric morphism and to connected topos that any connected geometric morphism is surjective.
I find the hypothesis “ is ” curious. I would have expected instead something like “ is sober and is ”, with the proof proceeding by regarding a point of as a point of , lifting it somehow to a point of , and using sobriety to extract a point of , whose image in is isomorphic to the original one, hence equal by . Actually it seems that would only use the “other half” of sobriety for (existence of points rather than their uniqueness). Is there a chance of such an argument also working?
For what it’s worth, I will answer the question of #4: I will argue that epimorphisms in are just the surjections.
Suppose in is not surjective, and take a point . I will argue that every point of the ordinary topological pushout is closed, i.e., this pushout object lives in so that the evident fork
lives in . In that case, since but , we would conclude is not epic in .
So we must verify that each point of is closed. The points of are certain equivalence classes of points of , so we verify that the equivalence classes are closed in . But each equivalence class consists of either a single point (the case where the point doesn’t “come from ”), or two points (a point of the form living in the first summand , and the same but living in the second summand). But finite subsets of are closed since this space is , so all these equivalence classes are closed, and we are done.
1 to 7 of 7