Want to take part in these discussions? Sign in if you have an account, or apply for one below
Vanilla 1.1.10 is a product of Lussumo. More Information: Documentation, Community Support.
1 to 12 of 12
Right properness and cofibrant generation are two very desirable properties of model categories. There are plenty of interesting examples of both right proper and non-proper model categories, while most model categories of interest are cofibrantly generated. On the other hand, for many cofibrantly generated model structures, “explicit” sets of generating acyclic cofibrations are not known. Of course, the word “explicit” has no technical meaning here, I mean sets that can be somehow enumerated (not necessarily in the computational sense) rather than described by phrases like “all acyclic cofibrations between objects of cardinality bounded by…”.
Now, it seems to me that there is a strange coincidence between our inability to write down explicit sets of generating acyclic cofibrations and failure of right properness. Hence the following somewhat vague questions.
Actually, I can give a boring answer to 1: certain injective model structures on diagrams in right proper model categories. I’m calling this a boring example since the corresponding projective model structure will have an explicit set of generating acyclic cofibrations and properness depends only on weak equivalences. Perhaps a more interesting example could be constructed using Bousfield localization. Here, I mean not the Smith style Bousfield localization, but one described e.g. in Section X.4 of Goerss–Jardine. This construction yields right proper model categories, but says nothing about cofibrant generation (although the examples I can think of at the moment happen to be explicitly cofibrantly generated).
I don’t know any answers to 2.
Here’s another answer to 1.
Let be a locally presentable category, let be a small dense full subcategory of , let be the Yoneda representation, and let be the reflector. We have the following model structure on :
This is, of course, a left Bousfield localisation of the “discrete” model structure on . It is right proper if and only if preserves pullbacks along fibrations. In particular, if is a Grothendieck topos, then (by Giraud’s theorem) we have a right proper model structure. I am not aware of any nice generating set of trivial cofibrations, but Smith’s theorem applies, so for some regular cardinal , the set of all trivial cofibrations (= weak equivalences) between presheaves with elements is a generating set.
Left Bousfield localization tends to destroy right-properness, so there should be many examples of (2).
Here is one important example. The complete Segal space model structure on simplicial spaces has completely explicit generating cofibrations and generating acyclic cofibrations, but it is not right proper:
http://mathoverflow.net/a/40967/184
Thanks for an example Zhen Lin. That’s something a bit unusual to me, so I will have to think about it for a while.
Chris, my understanding is that left Bousfield localizations rarely come with explicit generating acyclic cofibrations even if they are localizations at explicit sets of maps. Can you actually point me to a proof showing that the obvious set of acyclic cofibrations in the Rezk model structure generates all acyclic cofibrations? I used to think that this is true, but then I realized that this set detects only so called “injective maps” that coincide with fibrations only between fibrant objects, but in order to detect general fibrations you will have to throw in a lot more stuff. At least this is what happens in the Goerss–Jardine account which is what Rezk quotes when he constructs his model structure.
I’m not aware of explicit generating acyclic cofibrations for complete Segal spaces; the situation is as Karol says, I believe.
Do any of the models for (infty,1)-categories have explicit generating acyclic cofibrations? I can’t think of any.
Charles, thank you for a confirmation. I thought that this was the case but I wasn’t quite sure.
I also can’t think of any models of -categories with explicit generating acyclic cofibrations. This actually reminded me of another answer to question 1 (perhaps the most interesting one so far), the Bergner model structure on simplicial categories is right proper.
Here’s a proof that the “usual” acyclic cofibrations don’t generate all acyclic cofibrations in CSS.
Space := simplicial set. := free simplicial space on one point in degree n. := discrete nerve of the walking isomorphism; , a discrete space with two points. There is a standard inclusion , representing a map .
The “usual” acyclic cofibrations are the box products of either (i) the Segal maps or (i) the inclusion , with the standard simplicial cells .
Here’s something interesting about . Given a simplical space , think about . Of the elements of , the ones which can change when you glue them to are (which adds a point to ) and (which can identify two points of ). (The Segal maps are already bijections on -spaces, and the box product of a simplicial -cell with attaches an -cell to the -space.)
Let be the pushout of the diagram
So is the “walking 2-out-of-6 diagram”. It is weakly equivalent to the terminal object in the CSS model structure, and the inclusion is a CSS acyclic cofibration. I’m going to show that is not in the saturation of .
By the small object argument, there exists a factorization where is in the saturation of , and has the RLP with respect to . Note that since consists of acyclic cofibrations, both and will be w.e. in the CSS model structure. Furthermore, if the saturation of includes all acyclic cofibrations, this includes . In this case admits a section by lifting properties. In particular, must induce a surjective map .
Now we have a problem. The only way to add to is to attach . But all maps must send into either or (because there are points such that and ; however, there are no such that ). This means that no factorization with in the saturation of can give a surjection . This is a contradiction.
Of course, there is a simple fix whenever you have a counterexample like this: replace with . Now you get to ask the same question about …
Regarding a model for (∞,1)-categories with explicit generating acyclic cofibrations, what about algebraic quasicategories? In the direct construction of their model structure by transfer, the generating acyclic cofibrations would be the images by the free functor of the generating acyclic cofibrations for the Joyal model structure, and hence not explicit. But I think since fibrations of algebraic quasicategories are created by the forgetful functor, every algebraic quasicategory is in particular a quasicategory, and there is an explicit set of generating acyclic cofibrations for fibrations between fibrant objects in the Joyal model structure, we should be able to get an explicit set of generating acyclic cofibrations for algebraic quasicategories by applying the free functor to the latter set.
In general, it seems common (in particular, I think it’s true in all left Bousfield localizations) to have an explicit set of generating acyclic cofibrations for fibrations between fibrant objects. So the “algebraicization” technique should apply to other nonalgebraic models, like CSS, to give other algebraic models with an explicit set of generating acyclic cofibrations. I also wonder about a model in which all objects are naturally fibrant, like topologically enriched categories.
This doesn’t answer the original question (2), though, since when all objects are fibrant, right properness is automatic.
(Of course, one might object that free algebraic quasicategories are themselves not very explicit. But the set of generators is explicit; and more importantly, by adjunction, it gives an explicit criterion for an arbitrary map in the category to be a fibration.)
That’s a nice observation, Mike.
That’s an interesting thought, Mike. And I think it also gives a quite general recipe for “fixing” problems with Bousfield localizations we discussed above. The theorem of Nikolaus only requires a model structure where cofibrations are monomorphisms. If we have such a category and we know that the Bousfield localization at an explicit set of maps exists, then we have an explicit set of maps detecting local objects (at least if we had an explicit set detecting fibrant objects in the original category). The theorem turns them into generating acyclic cofibrations in the associated “algebraic” model structure.
Right. Although it does tend to destroy other nice properties of nonalgebraic model categories, like being a presheaf category, being lccc, or having all objects cofibrant. Model category theory is like playing whack-a-mole.
1 to 12 of 12