Want to take part in these discussions? Sign in if you have an account, or apply for one below
Vanilla 1.1.10 is a product of Lussumo. More Information: Documentation, Community Support.
I added a remark to inhabited set that one can regard writing to mean “ is inhabited” as a reference to an inequality relation on sets other than denial.
Nice observation!
Looking at that entry reminded me of a situation where the constructively sensible rendition of inhabitation is in fact non-emptiness. Let be an -scheme (in a classical context), which we visualize as an -indexed family of schemes. Recall that the functor of points of , , is an object of the big Zariski topos of and that the internal language of that topos is in all interesting cases not Boolean.
Then is set-theoretically surjective, meaning that all its fibers are inhabited, if and only if from the point of view of the Zariski topos, is not empty.
(The condition that is inhabited from the internal point of view means something much stronger, namely that the projection locally has a section, so that not only individual points of lift, but entire open parts.)
Nice example. In general, I find that the traditional constructivist antipathy towards logical negation is unnecessary. Often it is better to rephrase things “positively”, but plenty of sensible constructive notions do involve negation. For instance, the notion of “disjoint sets” involves a negation, and the inequality of real numbers can be defined as .
I agree. (Of course, a practical reason for tending to prefer positive formulations is that those are one step closer to being geometric formulas, which in turn are nice because they behave excellently under pullback along geometric morphisms. For anyone secretly following this conservation, but not quite grasping the importance of geometricity, I recommend Steve Vicker’s notes on this topic.)
True. Of course, negative definitions can also occur in geometric theories, since is a geometric sequent.
1 to 5 of 5