Not signed in (Sign In)

Not signed in

Want to take part in these discussions? Sign in if you have an account, or apply for one below

  • Sign in using OpenID

Site Tag Cloud

2-category 2-category-theory abelian-categories adjoint algebra algebraic algebraic-geometry algebraic-topology analysis analytic-geometry arithmetic arithmetic-geometry book bundles calculus categorical categories category category-theory chern-weil-theory cohesion cohesive-homotopy-type-theory cohomology colimits combinatorics complex complex-geometry computable-mathematics computer-science constructive cosmology deformation-theory descent diagrams differential differential-cohomology differential-equations differential-geometry digraphs duality elliptic-cohomology enriched fibration foundation foundations functional-analysis functor gauge-theory gebra geometric-quantization geometry graph graphs gravity grothendieck group group-theory harmonic-analysis higher higher-algebra higher-category-theory higher-differential-geometry higher-geometry higher-lie-theory higher-topos-theory homological homological-algebra homotopy homotopy-theory homotopy-type-theory index-theory integration integration-theory internal-categories k-theory lie-theory limits linear linear-algebra locale localization logic mathematics measure measure-theory modal modal-logic model model-category-theory monad monads monoidal monoidal-category-theory morphism motives motivic-cohomology nlab noncommutative noncommutative-geometry number-theory of operads operator operator-algebra order-theory pages pasting philosophy physics pro-object probability probability-theory quantization quantum quantum-field quantum-field-theory quantum-mechanics quantum-physics quantum-theory question representation representation-theory riemannian-geometry scheme schemes set set-theory sheaf simplicial space spin-geometry stable-homotopy-theory stack string string-theory superalgebra supergeometry svg symplectic-geometry synthetic-differential-geometry terminology theory topology topos topos-theory tqft type type-theory universal variational-calculus

Vanilla 1.1.10 is a product of Lussumo. More Information: Documentation, Community Support.

Welcome to nForum
If you want to take part in these discussions either sign in now (if you have an account), apply for one now (if you don't).
    • CommentRowNumber101.
    • CommentAuthorDmitri Pavlov
    • CommentTimeAug 30th 2021
    • (edited Aug 31st 2021)

    Re #100: Dugger’s theorem does prove homotopical essential surjectivity, equivalently, essential surjectivity for 2-localizations like in Renaudin’s paper.

    But what do you want to do for 1-morphisms and 2-morphisms? More generally, how do you intend to prove homotopical fully faithfulness?

    In terms of hammock localizations, one would need to show that the induced inclusion of hammock localizations is a weak equivalence.

    This is hardly obvious since a hammock between two left proper combinatorial model categories can pass through non-left proper combinatorial model categories.

    • CommentRowNumber102.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeAug 30th 2021

    Okay, I see. So it’s good that you are looking into this in detail!

    Have adjusted the footnote at Ho(CombModCat) and copied it also to derivator.

    But please feel invited to further edit as need be.

    • CommentRowNumber103.
    • CommentAuthorDmitri Pavlov
    • CommentTimeOct 9th 2021

    The draft is ready: https://dmitripavlov.org/comb.pdf. 31 pages!

    Perhaps you could take a look and see whether the statement you wanted is present in one of the 4 theorems?

    • CommentRowNumber104.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeOct 9th 2021

    Ah, excellent! I have now read the introduction section 1. Looks good!

    Yes, I was after your Theorem 1.4 with presentable quasicategories instead of derivators, but of course your theorems 1.1/1.2 are much stronger than what I was looking for.

    Just to check if I am reading right: the items in theorems 1.1 and 1.2 are all DW-equivalent to each other, right? Since the lists share the first item, CMC (though in 1.2 it’s not referred to as CMC).

    • CommentRowNumber105.
    • CommentAuthorDmitri Pavlov
    • CommentTimeOct 9th 2021

    Re #104: Yes, certainly. Will fix this now.

    • CommentRowNumber106.
    • CommentAuthorDmitri Pavlov
    • CommentTimeOct 9th 2021

    Do you have any similar statements in mind that you would like to see included?

    • CommentRowNumber107.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeOct 9th 2021

    Maybe if you could just make explicit the corollary that, in particular, the homotopy 2-category of CMC is equivalent to that of Pres\inftyCat, just so that the reader sees fully manifestly that you have, in particular, adapted Renaudin’s theorem from presentable derivators to presentable \infty-categories.

    • CommentRowNumber108.
    • CommentAuthorDmitri Pavlov
    • CommentTimeOct 10th 2021

    Re #107: Done, see the new statement of Theorem 1.4 in the newly uploaded file.

    Let me know if you can think of any other useful statements that could be added.

    (The theorems that establish these results allow for a lot of variation.)

    • CommentRowNumber109.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeOct 10th 2021

    Looks good, thanks.

    If I were to freely wish for more: How about locally cartesian closed presentable \infty-categories and any of their model category presentations listed here?

    • CommentRowNumber110.
    • CommentAuthorDmitri Pavlov
    • CommentTimeOct 10th 2021

    Re #109: Yes, this appears to be true.

    The argument continues to work in a similar way, except that a slightly different model must be chosen.

    Looking at the proofs of Cisinski and Gepner–Kock, I see that their construction of rectification is similar to mine, but instead of presenting κ-compact objects as a small relative category and then taking simplicial presheaves and left Bousfield localizing to ind-complete, they present κ-compact objects as a small fibrant simplicial category, take simplicial presheaves, and left Bousfield localize to ind-complete.

    So either one has to show that the proofs of Cisinski and Gepner–Kock continue to work in my setting (for instance, showing that Proposition 1.5 in the Gepner–Kock paper continues to work if we use presheaves on a relative category of κ-compact objects), or, alternatively, establish a variant of my theorem for their version of this construction, which requires writing a new variant of Section 7 in my paper (4 pages total).

    Can you think of any applications that would justify writing this up as a separate note? Something from type theory, perhaps?

    • CommentRowNumber111.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeOct 10th 2021
    • (edited Oct 10th 2021)

    I should say that the reason I brought this up in the first place is that I want to use it:

    We are writing something like a book on matters of cohesive \infty-bundles and are facing the tension between being both reasonably self-contained as well as reasonably concise. But the content-module “model category theory” is meant to have been loaded already, and so I was thinking about the quickest way from here to actually and rigorously setting up modal \infty-topos theory. So I need a quick yet correct way to characterize the homotopy 2-category of presentable \infty-categories (and then of presentable LCC \infty-categories, etc.) based on just model category theory (okay, and localization of (2,1)(2,1)-categories). Which is what you now provided! :-)

    I am thinking that this way of laying working foundations for \infty-category theory should be quite useful in general.

    But maybe you are looking for a more specific application. Regarding homotopy type theory: I’d have to remind myself of the details of what this article accomplishes:

    but broadly this should be the kind of consideration that would benefit from a good understanding of the simplicial localization of CMC and LCCMC. (Checking the citations this has picked up, I am getting the impression that this is still essentially the state of the art, but I haven’t been following closely).

    • CommentRowNumber112.
    • CommentAuthorDmitri Pavlov
    • CommentTimeOct 10th 2021

    Okay, this is something I could write up separately, although maybe not in 2021, but in 2022.

    • CommentRowNumber113.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeOct 11th 2021

    Okay, sounds good! :-)

    • CommentRowNumber114.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeOct 11th 2021

    It’s a little unfortunate that we ended up having this whole discussion here under “derivator”, when it all originated from (and now succeeded in) the quest at Ho(CombModCat) to go away from the case of derivators. In any case, I have now added pointer to your draft there. I hope we eventually get the main results recorded there.

    • CommentRowNumber115.
    • CommentAuthorDmitri Pavlov
    • CommentTimeOct 12th 2021

    It is now on arXiv: https://arxiv.org/abs/2110.04679

    • CommentRowNumber116.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeOct 12th 2021

    Good.

    By the way, how hard would it be to enhance to an equivalence of homotopy 2-categories or (,2)(\infty,2)-categories? (i.e. as opposed to just homotopy (2,1)(2,1)-categories or (,1)(\infty,1)-categories)?

    • CommentRowNumber117.
    • CommentAuthorDmitri Pavlov
    • CommentTimeOct 12th 2021

    Re #116: Not difficult. In fact, I was thinking about adding the version with noninvertible 2-morphisms, but decided against it, because while straightforward to write it would make the paper longer.

    Basically, you need to develop some (straightforward) stuff about relative 2-categories (or 2-relative 2-categories?), where the hom-object hom(X,Y) is a relative category (objects are 1-morphisms, morphisms are 2-morphism), and some 1-morphism and 2-morphisms are weak equivalence.

    In our case, left Quillen equivalences are weak 1-equivalences and natural transformations that are weak equivalences on cofibrant objects are weak 2-equivalences.

    So the 2-categorical statement is true, and not difficult to write up, but the paper was already 32 pages long, so I decided against it.

    This can also be done as a separate paper, if there is interest in it.

    • CommentRowNumber118.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeOct 12th 2021

    That would be great to have the 2-category-version written up somewhere! As highlighted by Riehl-Verity, the homotopy 2-category of infinity-categories goes a long way. In particular it knows all about the adjoints, hence the modalities, that I’d particularly care about.

    • CommentRowNumber119.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeOct 13th 2021

    Regarding the “2-relative” in #117:

    Renaudin speaks only about 2-localizing at 1-morphisms.

    I am guessing the point is that this inverts the desired 2-morphisms (“Quillen homotopies”) because (his Prop. 2.1.4, p. 10) these are equivalently 1-morphisms into the arrow category of the domain, equipped with a suitable model structure (his modèle chemin in Sec. 2.1.1).

    Is that right? I haven’t penetrated further into his proof.

    (Nor yours for that matter. I did spend some time with your article yesterday, but it was a surprising lot of discussion of techniques for dealing with size issues, and I haven’t yet gotten beyond these to the bottom of the proof yet.)

    But disregarding details of the proof, what’s the form of the statement to be expected? Is it the 2-localization of the 2-category of combinatorial model categories at the 1-morphisms that are left Quillen equivalences which is already going to be equivalent to the homotopy 2-category of presentable \infty-categories? Or only after further 1-localizing this hom-category-wise at the Quillen homotopies?

    • CommentRowNumber120.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeOct 13th 2021

    Sorry, I am being stupid. After I wrote this comment I remembered that I had made a note on this in the entry here: Renaudin’s theorem 2.3.2 says that the 2-morphisms which are Quillen homotopies automatically get inverted once the 1-morphisms which are left Quillen euqivalences have been inverted.

    • CommentRowNumber121.
    • CommentAuthorDmitri Pavlov
    • CommentTimeOct 13th 2021

    Re #120: Indeed, even more directly, Proposition 2.1.4 shows how to convert Quillen homotopies to left Quillen functors into path model categories, whereas Corollary 2.1.5 immediately applies Proposition 2.1.4 to show that inverting left Quillen equivalences also inverts Quillen homotopies, since the “constant path” left Quillen functor is a left Quillen equivalence.

    So indeed we only need a “1-relative 2-category”, where only left Quillen equivalences need to be inverted.

    Now that I think about it, it can be even easier to prove than I thought.

    I think hammock localizations can be easily adapted to work with 1-relative 2-categories (each square in a hammock now has to commute up to a possibly noninvertible 2-morphism), and the hammock construction now produces a category enriched in simplicial sets equipped with the Joyal model structure.

    • CommentRowNumber122.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeOct 13th 2021

    Thanks, great.

    Let me just double check about the form of the theorem you think you can prove:

    Let me write

    • 2Loc ()2Loc_{(-)} for 2-localization of 2-categories at a class of 1-morphisms, as in Renaudin’s article

    • 2Ho()2Ho(-) for the homotopy 2-category of an (,2)(\infty,2)-category.

    Then there ought to be an equivalence of 2-categories:

    2Loc QuEqu(CombModCat)2Ho(PresCat) 2Loc_{QuEqu}\big( CombModCat \big) \;\; \simeq \;\; 2Ho \big( Pres \infty Cat \big)
    • CommentRowNumber123.
    • CommentAuthorDmitri Pavlov
    • CommentTimeOct 13th 2021
    • (edited Oct 13th 2021)

    Re #122: Yes, and I think this equivalence of 2-categories is induced by taking the homotopy 2-categories of the analogous equivalence of (∞,2)-categories, modeled as categories enriched in simplicial sets with the Joyal model structure, where the homotopy 2-category construction replaces each hom-object with its fundamental category.

    The hom-objects can be constructed like in the usual hammock localization, but with 2-morphisms thrown in for each commuting square.

    • CommentRowNumber124.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeOct 14th 2021

    Thanks, great.

    Mulling further about how to use this, I come to think that what I really want is closed symmetric monoidal structure on the 1-category Loc QuEqCombModCatLoc^{QuEq} CombModCat. That should be guaranteed as the 1-cat shadow of the closed symmetric structure on PresCatPres \infty Cat, though it would be nice to have explicit model category theoretic presentation for it. The (strict) 2-category structure would be implied.

    (This is not meant to be in reply to anything, I am just thinking out loud.)

    • CommentRowNumber125.
    • CommentAuthorperezl.alonso
    • CommentTimeSep 12th 2023

    Added last night’s:

    diff, v73, current

    • CommentRowNumber126.
    • CommentAuthorUrs
    • CommentTimeSep 12th 2023
    • (edited Sep 12th 2023)

    have hyperlinked the author name (here) and added the reference to his page: Nicola Di Vittorio

    diff, v74, current